|
This review has been accessed times since May 17, 2002
Curren, Randall R. (2000). Aristotle on the Necessity of
Public Education. New York: Rowman & Littlefield
Publishers, Inc.
256 pp.
$27.95 (Paper) ISBN: 0-8476-9673-1
$79.50 (Cloth) ISBN: 0-8476-9672-3
Reviewed by Jana Noel
California State University, Sacramento
May 17, 2002
A renewed interest in Aristotle has become
apparent in a number of recent examinations and re-examinations
of Aristotle by moral philosophers as well as feminists (such as
Freeland 1998; Natali 2001; Tessitore 1996). Much of this recent
work has focused on Aristotelian conceptions of ethics, politics,
and justice. But there is a lack of scholarship on the
importance that Aristotle places on the ideal of public education
itself. Randall Curren's book fills this gap within the
field of Aristotelian scholarship.
Curren's purpose for his book is to provide
a "reconstruction of Aristotle's neglected account of
education and its place in public life" (p. ix). Curren
draws this reconstruction from Aristotle's views about
political and ethical life, and focuses on the relationships
between law, virtue, and education. Curren then uses this
analysis to frame his discussion of contemporary issues such as
educational equity and the moral content of education.
This book pulls together Curren's previous
work of over a decade. Several chapters in the book are revised
versions of previous articles and presentations on Aristotelian
politics and ethics. He draws mainly from the Politics
and the Nicomachean Ethics, though he must reconstruct
arguments which come from various remarks about education that
have been scattered throughout several texts in order to make
more clear for the reader the argument Aristotle is making for
public education.
Reviewer's Conclusions
Curren is solidly grounded in philosophy, education,
and
political thought. In his book, Curren has successfully,
interestingly, and effectively succeeded in his goals for his
book. The text is both highly philosophical and mainly readable
by a reader who lacks background in Aristotle.
Criticisms that will be laid out in this review lie
less in
the arguments undertaken by Curren and more in his approach to
reading Aristotle. Curren presents his reconstruction of
Aristotle through a political reading first and foremost. When
he discusses moral and intellectual virtues, he discusses them in
terms of their usefulness for creating and maintaining the law.
However, another reading would be to present the reconstruction
through an ethical analysis first, with politics coming later.
This would put the discussion of education as contributing to the
development of moral and intellectual virtues first, rather than
emphasizing their contribution to law.
I must agree with Emily Robertson (2002), who stated
that
perhaps the reason why Curren places such a heavy importance on
the political and legal framework for his discussion of education
is because it would likely carry more weight with the
policymakers that he would like to reach. The moral and ethical
content of such education, which he puts a lesser emphasis upon,
could be addressed more to the practitioners of education, the
teachers.
Other criticisms will focus on Aristotle's and
Curren's version of multicultural education as well as
Curren's interpretation that education for employment would
fulfill Aristotle's vision of justice.
Main Points
This review will focus on three main points
– principles and arguments – within Curren's
book. These points will be introduced here, followed by a
summary of the points in each chapter that contribute to those
arguments.
First, Curren remains consistently faithful to
what he terms the principle of fidelity to reason. As
Curren defines it, this principle has two main components: a
respect for reason within ourselves and others, and the idea that
instruction and persuasion must come before force. Curren
introduces this in his first chapter, and consistently reinforces
its importance throughout his discussion of Aristotle.
Second, Curren in Chapter 3 (p. 80) lays out four
main arguments regarding Aristotle's necessity of
education. These four arguments frame the discussion in the rest
of the work, and provide what I believe to be the most unique
contribution of Curren's work in his discussions of
Aristotle's vision of public education. These arguments
come directly from Aristotle's Politics 1337,
dividing 1337a10-31 into four distinct arguments, which he then
labels and discusses in sections throughout the rest of his
book. Curren is careful to discuss each argument distinctly,
while also drawing the connections that necessarily link them all
in Aristotle's sense of education. The four arguments are
as follows:
1) "The Argument from Constitutional Requirements
(CR). The neglect of education in polises harms their
constitutions. The young should be educated toward each
constitution, for the character proper to each both safeguards it
and establishes it to begin with…And in all cases better
character produces a better constitution (1337a10-18)."
2) "The Argument from the Origins of Virtue
(OV). Again, for the exercise of any faculty or art a prior
education and habituation are required; clearly therefore [these
are required] for the practice of virtue (1337a18-21)."
3) "The Argument from a Common End (CE). And
since the whole city has one end, it is manifest that education
should be one and the same for all, and its care public and not
private…The training in things which are of common
interest should be made common (1337a21-27)."
4) "The Argument from Inseparability (I). At
the
same time, one should not suppose that any of the citizens
belongs to himself, but rather that each belongs to the
polis…and it is natural for the care of each part to look
to the care of the whole (1337a27-31)."
So Curren reconstructs these passages to claim that an
argument for public education needs to consider 1) the
relationship between character and the law, 2) the need for moral
habituation into virtuous actions, 3) that the goal or end for
the city is a unified end for all, and 4) that the whole of the
polis should take part in the care of all.
Third, Curren's main conclusion is that his
argument from the foundations of corrective justice (FCJ),
which he develops throughout his book, provides the best argument
for providing a public education. This argument says that part
of the existence of the state is the providing of law and
punishment. For the state to be able to expect its citizens to
follow the law, and for itself to be able to hand out punishments
justly, there must be some universal education for citizens to
understand the law and develop the character needed to follow the
law.
In summary, then, Curren provides a reconstruction
of Aristotle's arguments, describing how education, virtue,
and law are virtually intertwined. He then concludes that
educational equity comes when citizens are educated together in
order to work toward the best for the society.
Chapter 1: "Greek Paideia and Socratic
Principles"
Curren begins in Chapter 1 with a discussion of
whether the city has the right or the imperative to punish
wrongdoers. Curren's response to this question is to claim
that the first consideration is whether the wrongdoer has first
been instructed in the laws of the city and in what should be the
aim of the city – the good for the city and its people.
Instruction should enable, as well, defiance of "bad
law" by citizens who have learned how to determine if a law
is worthy of following. If educational efforts fail to delete
ignorance and wrongdoing, then the city should retain the right
to punish. But first must come the instruction.
This, then, is where we see the beginning of the focus
on what
he is going to call the principle of fidelity to reason,
which states that instruction and persuasion should come before
force. As Curren writes, "Cities cannot justly demand the
loyalty or voluntary obedience of citizens without creating the
conditions for free and informed consent to their laws, nor can
they establish a general right to punish lawbreakers without
providing for the education of all citizens" (p. 34). The
focus here is on reason, which is required in order to understand
law. But Curren does include an ethical discussion as well, when
he writes that since "The natural aim of a city is the
highest good of its citizens, which consists of being wise, or
having and exercising systematic moral knowledge"(p. 33),
then cities should also encourage education related to the
development of moral knowledge.
Chapter 2: "The Arguments of Plato"
In Chapter 2, Curren writes of the relationship
between moral education and reason, within the realm of political
science. Curren begins a discussion on the need for reason to
overcome the passions, bringing in Protagoras' statements
that those who are educated to have their reasoning overcome
their passions are better than those whom he calls savages. But
to help reason in its attempt to "prevail over the
passions," it needs the support of ethical virtues such as
phronesis and justice. But as Curren discusses these virtues at
this point, they are not meaningful in themselves. Rather, in
the Protagoras and the Republic, these are
"essential means to the flourishing of reason"
(p. 54).
Curren describes one of the educational
undertakings that must occur for this self-control to develop.
In a theme that is seen in Aristotle as well, Plato concludes
that there must be a form of censorship with our youth in order
for them to become fully morally developed. They should learn to
admire what is admirable, learn to hate what is shameful, and
learn to make these proper judgments. This will give them
practice in being law-abiding.
Such censorship is one form of education for moral
improvement. Curren distinguishes between the dialectic
reasoning that can be undertaken by an elite group, such as the
philosopher-kings of the Republic, and the non-elenctic
form of reasoning that would provide a larger set of citizens
with the opportunity to gain more complete moral development.
This education could come from "divinely inspired
lawgivers" who will teach the self-control needed that will
make people "supremely easy to persuade along the path of
virtue" (Laws, IV 718c) (p. 56). For Plato, the
purpose of education is to provide "education from
childhood in virtue, a training which produces a keen desire to
become a perfect citizen who knows how to rule and be ruled as
justice demands" (I 643e-44a) (p. 57).
Chapter 3: Groundwork for an Interpretation of Politics
VIII.1
Curren begins his formal analysis of
Aristotle's works in Chapter 3. His introduction of
Socratic and Platonic principles in Chapters 1 and 2 lead well
into his discussion of Aristotle. This is the chapter in which
Curren introduces his four arguments described at the beginning
of this review"The Argument from Constitutional
Requirements (CR), "The Argument from the Origins of
Virtue (OV), "The Argument from a Common End
(CE), and "The Argument from Inseparability
(I). In addition, this chapter addresses the relationship
between the state and education, the content of education, and
how citizens can receive an education to take part in rule.
A very good conceptual analysis related to levels
of regulation ensues on pp. 86-87. In this section, Curren
proposes that perhaps the role of the state in education could be
to sponsor education, or more strongly to mandate it by law, or
finally even stronger to control what people do in both education
and society. Curren believes that the mandating of specific
instruction has been dismissed through his analysis in the text.
He concludes this analysis by saying that Aristotle may have been
saying indirectly in the Politics VIII that the state
should sponsor mandatory instruction as well as exercise
broad control, through law, over how people act.
In discussing levels of regulation, Curren also
addresses the question of how ordinary citizens can become a part
of the rule-giving in the state. Curren brings in the concept of
phronesis, an ethical concept usually translated as practical
wisdom. Curren describes Aristotle's view when he states
that a greater right to share in rule comes with a greater share
of practical wisdom, thus education should guide students toward
the having of virtue, of phronesis.
And finally, Curren ends his Chapter 3 with an initial
foray
into the issue of educational equity. Aristotle, famously,
argues that slaves are needed in the economy and that women
should not be engaged in a public life. But in regards to the
possibility of an education for all people, Aristotle is less
clear. Curren proposes that while the city will only consider
citizens to be equal partners in the creation of eudemonia
– which is the good end for the city – it is still
possible to interpret Aristotle as claiming that we should
"regard all inhabitants of a city as entitled to share in
some of its benefits that will promote their well-being"
(p. 91). But these inhabitants could not be equal partners, and
thus would not receive an equal education to male citizens.
Curren concludes that all male citizens, regardless of social
status, would "receive the same liberal education, which
provides what is necessary of the practical arts, cultivates
virtue, and aims above all to nurture the capacities of reason
and intellect" (p. 92).
Chapter 4: "Why Education is Important"
Chapter 4 is directly about what it claims to be
about: why education is important. In this chapter, Curren
further elaborates the arguments from the origins of virtue
(OV), then continues to point out the connections between the
OV and the argument from constitutional requirements
(CR). The main point of this chapter seems to be the laying
out for us how the various arguments fit together.
Curren's argument from the origins of
virtue (OV) states that both instruction and moral
habituation lead to virtue. Curren expands this discussion with
a useful analysis of three possible sub-arguments of the OV
argument.
1) The Argument from a City's Natural
End. In this argument, Curren argues, "the natural aim
of a polis and of political science is the highest good for human
beings," which is a life in accordance with the highest
virtue. But since "The practice of virtue requires prior
education and habituation (OV)," then the polis must
require education.
2) The Appeal to Respect for Reason. Human
beings naturally need "to respect the reason in themselves
and others." This also, though, "entails a duty to
encourage and cultivate one's own and other's
rationality." And since "the cultivation of a human
being's potential rationality entails the cultivation of
virtue and requires education (OV)," then the polis must
require education.
3) The Argument from the Promotion of
Happiness. "Legislators should promote the happiness
of all citizens as much as possible." And since promoting
citizens' happiness must also entail promoting their
virtue, and since "The practice of virtue requires
education and habituation (OV)," then the polis and its
legislators must require education. (pp. 94-96)
Taken together, these three arguments create the
claim that public education is required because it contributes to
the city's natural end, because it creates a respect for
reason, and because it helps to promote happiness.
Next Curren elaborates further on his previously
laid out argument from constitutional requirements (CR).
In what Curren calls the appeal to a desire for stable
rule, if a legislator is going to be persuaded to work toward
the good of the city's citizens, then there needs to be an
appeal to his self-interest. The push within this argument is
for legislators and citizens alike to value education. Educating
toward better character will promote a better constitution, with
the long-term outcome being "a stable orderliness in
society" (p. 110), or constitutional stability.
And toward the end of this chapter, Curren ties
Aristotle's rather well-known dictum of moderation in all
things to contemporary education, as the book moves more and more
toward tying the reconstruction into the contemporary debates
about education. For the discussion of educational equity which
permeates the book, Curren focuses on moderation of wealth.
Curren ties Aristotle's concept of moderation to a better
political environment:
Aristotle would seem to hold that education is
important
to
securing a number of constitutional goods which contribute
in turn to a city's capacity to promote the best life
for its
citizens: good order; stability; moderation or relative
equality
in wealthy; just, wise, and equitably distributed governance;
and
unity or social harmony. (p. 112)
Chapter 5: "Why Education Should Be Public and the
Same for All"
Chapter Five is, I believe, the easiest chapter to read
for
laypersons, because it addresses contemporary topics such as
pluralism in a discussion style, and less in an analytic style
which follows textually the words of Aristotle. It does,
however, also present some of the most problematic concepts of
Aristotelian thought, related to the desire to have everyone be
virtually the same in their views, ideas, and virtues.
Curren uses another new argument here, the argument
from
constitutional unity (CU), which he then combines with his
earlier stated argument from a common end (CE). These
arguments, together, claim that to reach and maintain a
political, constitutional unity, there must be a common end that
all should aim to reach. Aristotle wants to use "vehicles
of civic unification" (p. 131), such as brotherhoods,
common rites, and education, to create bonds of friendship in
order to reach this common end. Curren claims that Aristotle
would especially emphasize a common education as a force for
promoting that common end and toward unity, since education can
"bring citizens together in settings which nurture friendly
contact, common desires and character traits, and the formation
of networks of substantial friendships spanning the city's
disparate social and economic sectors. (p. 131)
This brings to mind the efforts at desegregation, such
as
busing and intergroup education, that began in the 1950s-1960s as
a way to bring students from different races together. However,
while some of the goals for these efforts were to help students
initiate understanding and friendships based on differences,
rather than trying to erase differences, Aristotle has an
entirely different end in mind. As Curren interprets Aristotle,
the goal of educating children together is to create a unified
community by making people as alike as possible: "A
‘common upbringing,' which makes people more alike,
‘contributes greatly to friendship' (NE
VIII.12 1161b34-35)" (p. 137). This language is
disturbingly reminiscent of the language used at the turn of the
beginning of the 20th century in America, both in
debates about immigration restriction and by educators. While
Aristotle writes that "every contrivance should be adopted
which will mingle the citizens with one another and get rid of
old connections (NE VI.4 1319b23-27)" (p. 139), a
New York superintendent of schools in 1918 wrote that schools
should teach children "an appreciation of the institutions
of this country [and] absolute forgetfulness of all obligations
or connections with other countries because of descent or
birth" (Tyack, 1993, p. 13). The impact of these attitudes
included the deculturalizationloss of cultureand
restriction of immigration all who were not Western European.
Curren does take some time to criticize this
argument from
a common end (CE). He addresses the very real concern in
contemporary society that there may be multiple goals within a
city, that there can be a "pluralism of the
good" (p. 140). Curren writes that this would result in a
less unified society than Aristotle envisioned, and that citizens
would share fewer "traits" and goals in common. But
Curren sticks with the Aristotelian line in this case, as he
calls the CE a way to "serve as a sufficient counterweight
to the centrifugal forces exerted by the presence of competing
conceptions of the good. (p. 140)
Next Curren moves to what he calls the argument from
inseparability (I), which is the level to which people belong
to the state vs. how much they can claim to belong to
themselves. Curren changes the question to how much "the
good of individuals as dependent upon the good of the whole
polis" (p. 145). Curren labels this the argument from
the unity of care. He describes that "the care of each
necessarily involves and must be guided by the care of the whole
because the care of each requires law, and law is an
essentially common institution which aims not at the good of any
one individual, but at the common good" (p. 149). Law and
education should be used together to reach the common good.
It is at this point that Curren further elaborates on
his
argument from the foundations of corrective justice
(FCJ). He divides this into the consent version and
the complicity version of FCJ. He has already begun
laying the groundwork for the idea of consent, with his
principle of fidelity to reason, which, again, states that
persuasion must come before force in order to gain consent for
the principles of justice. The complicity version of FCJ,
on the other hand, deals not with consent but with who is allowed
to punish and when. The complicity version is described
as follows: "it is the one in a position to educate and
punish – the state, or polis in its legislative capacities
– that is to blame, and not the wrongdoer, if the former
did not provide suitable education" (p. 151). Curren
describes Aristotle's contribution to this developing idea
as that while individual human beings must give individual effort
to their own moral and intellectual development, in reality it is
the polis as a whole that must also contribute the proper
training and habituation toward moral development.
Chapter 6: "Education and the Foundations of
Justice"
After laying the groundwork for the argument
from corrective justice (FCJ) in Chapter 5, Curren moves in
Chapter 6 to further elaborate the argument, as well as to
respond to possible objects to this argument. The first main
line in this chapter is a response to the criticisms from the
private law/criminal law fields. Curren claims that writers from
these fields misinterpret Aristotle as conceiving of corrective
justice as distinct from and independent of distributive
justice. As Curren writes, it is important in criticizing these
contemporary writings to note that "for Aristotle
all law is an instrument of political rule, and none of it
private in the modern sense" (p. 159).
To deal with the second argument against his FCJ,
Curren engages in a discussion of Aristotle's account of
moral responsibility. Curren reminds us that any criticisms that
require a modern notion of free will are inaccurate readings of
Aristotle. For as Curren writes, for Aristotle, much of the
moral education of persons "must be produced by"
moral habituation toward rationally determining what actions to
take toward the good of the city (p. 161).
Curren tries to take a conciliatory approach based on
the
concepts of diagnostic and justificatory
judgments. In Curren's analysis, we should see
Aristotle's account of responsibility first as diagnostica
moral assessment of an actionand second as justificatoryan
injunction to impose sanctions for improper actions.
Curren again engages in a discussion of multicultural
issues
in today's society, when he returns to the complicity
version of FCJ. He describes that Aristotle's main
concern is over differing abilities to make informed and rational
consent due to "differential investments in moral
socialization" (p. 178). He proclaims that the
aggressiveness fostered in our school systems of today is that
this model "fails to cultivate a responsiveness to
reason" (italics in original) (p. 181), which is needed
in FCJ. This is a good conclusion to the argument is one is
reading the argument from the perspective of the principle of
fidelity to reason. Another response, from the focus on
care, would be that this model of aggressiveness does not provide
a model of caring that students would need in order to begin to
care for others in their shared polis.
Curren's conclusion to this chapter is this: "the
acquisition of a rational will, of self-control, and the capacity
to comply with law, is an attainment which requires timely and
very substantial social investments which are far from
universally forthcoming" (p. 181).
Chapter 7: "Justice and the Substance of Common
Care"
The final chapter of this book is the chapter that
most directly addresses education, and it is crucial for drawing
conclusions to the arguments set forth by Curren throughout the
book. It also presents more of Curren's own words,
including two graphs that help to further explain his ideas.
Some of the key points in this chapter include the nature of
educational equity and democracy, education toward full
employment, the role of phronesis in education, and finally, a
conclusion to the discussion of Aristotle on the necessity of
public education.
Curren begins this final analysis of educational
equality by laying out three difficulties with defining
educational equality. First, Curren writes, there are different
values and benefits within the world. In other words, not
everybody places value on the same things, and not everybody
benefits from the same things. Second, Curren engages in an
analysis of the concepts of "equal educational
opportunity" vs "equal education." The
difference here is in how the aims of education are conceived.
Equal education applies when there is an immediate instructional
task, while equal educational opportunity speaks to broader
goals. Curren lists some of the possible goals as
"equalization in prospects in life or prospects of
middle-class status, or more modestly the equalization of
opportunity to get an education that will improve those
prospects" (p. 185). And a third difficulty in defining
educational equality is the distribution of resources. Curren
leads this discussion into the domain of how much the state
should have the power or, further, be required to distribute
resources equally across all educational enterprises.
In examining these conceptions of educational
equality, Curren undertakes an extended analysis of Amy
Gutmann's concept of ‘democratic threshold' of
equal educational opportunity, in which she proposes a threshold
of equality rather than an absolute equality. Probably the
greatest concern that Curren expresses over Gutmann's ideas
is that the way she has conceived of educational equality drives
education toward being a competitive arena. Curren's
response, very clearly drawn from his reconstruction of Aristotle
thus far, is that education should be aimed at a common good, and
should be considered as a practice that aims for the common
good, not as a way to advance one group over another.
Curren argues that his argument from the foundations
of
corrective justice (FCJ), combined with the argument from
a common end (CE), will result in a rich compulsory
curriculum. Curren's version of a rich curriculum is
"one which includes moral and civic education, preparation
for work, and an initiation into the life of the mind focused on
the structures of reason and evidence" (p. 183). In this
new focus on education for work, Curren writes from
Aristotle's concept of moderation of wealth when he writes
that rule in society is undermined by inequities in economic
status. In practical terms, Curren interprets Aristotle as
having concern over the ability and desire to work together to
achieve a common end when there are gross economic
inequities.
Now this argument definitely shows a foundation in the
words
of Aristotle provided by Curren throughout the book. And I
appreciate the discussion of how economic viability impacts a
person's ability to participate in life. However, I would
challenge the argument. This focus on education for employment,
in reality, does not guarantee economic equality, and possibly
worse on Curren's account, neither does it guarantee
"the possibility of mutual respect." For even if
there were universal availability of work, it is not only the
unemployed who struggle to gain the mutual respect and trust of
others, but also those who work in jobs that may not be
universally respected by others, ranging from minimum wage work
to work in certain of the professions.
And now, in the middle of this final chapter,
Curren addresses more fully the concept of phronesis, which
Aristotle states absolutely must underlie virtue. As Curren
interprets Aristotle, "no one has true moral virtue without
having the intellectual virtue of practical wisdom" (p.
202). Since practical wisdom involves conceptions of the good as
well as deliberations about what actions to take to reach that
good, I believe that all of Curren's arguments regarding
virtue, common end, and understanding of the law, could be taken
to be based entirely on the possession of phronesis. For as
Curren concludes, phronesis is "the consummation of
virtue" (p. 204).
And finally, at the conclusion of the book, Curren
provides an argument for common schooling based on identifying
common goods that can be reached by educating all children
together. A common schooling would promote trust and friendship,
would enable all people to participate in decision-making for the
whole, and that the result would be "a more socially
unified and politically stable society" (p. 215). Curren
concludes this part of this discussion by writing that
Aristotle's concerns about social
division, distrust, inequality,
and the barriers these pose to a stable and just political
system
are significant enough to warrant establishing and
maintaining
a public system of schools which at least provides
substantial
incentives for children from all parts of our cities to spend
part
of their time learning and growing up together in settings
which
accord and communicate equality of status. (p. 216)
This argument answers, also, the question of whether
privatization of education would be valued in an Aristotelian
view. In Curren's analysis, with Aristotle's concern
that children be educated together in order to learn common
values and ideas, Curren believes that Aristotle would not have
been in favor of privatization schemes like vouchers.
This last argument, in my opinion, is the most
valuable in the book for understanding Aristotle's
arguments within contemporary terms. It helps explain, in terms
we use everyday, why Aristotle would say that public schools are
necessary.
References
Freeland, Cynthia (ed.) (1998). Feminist Interpretations
of Aristotle. University Park,
PA: The Pennsylvania State University Press.
Natali, Carlo (2001). The Wisdom of Aristotle.
Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
Robertson, Emily (May, 2002). "On the Necessity of
Public Education: Curren's
Argument from the Foundations of Corrective
Justice." Paper presented at the
California Association of Philosophers of
Education conference.
Tessitore, Aristide (1996). Reading Aristotle's
"Ethics": Virtue, Rhetoric, and Political
Philosophy. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
About the Reviewer
Jana Noel is an Assistant Professor of Educational Foundations
at California State University, Sacramento, after being Assistant
and Associate Professor of Multicultural Education and Philosophy
of Education for nine years at Montana State University. Her
research interests are in multicultural teacher education,
Aristotelian scholarship, and the history of Native American
education.
[ home |
overview | reviews | editors | submit | guidelines | announcements ]
| |