|
This review has been accessed times since October 7, 2002
Welner, Kevin (2001). Legal Rights, Local
Wrongs: When Community Control Collides with Educational
Equity. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press
315 pp.
$81.50 (hardback) ISBN 0-7914-5127-5
$27.95 (paperback) ISBN 0-7914-5128-3
Reviewed by Eric Haas
Arizona State University
October 7, 2002
In Legal Rights, Local Wrongs: When Community Control
Collides with Educational Equity (2001), Kevin Welner, a
lawyer with a Ph.D. in education policy, explores the role of
legal decisions in propelling equity-minded school reform.
Specifically, Welner examines court-ordered detracking, the
requirement that all classes within a school be mixed ability.
Welner sets out to examine how school reform is defined, how it
is measured, and the role of top-down legal mandates in moving a
reform forward. Welner hopes that Legal Rights, Local
Wrongs will explain the need for all members of the school
community—from parents to policymakers—to rededicate
themselves to pushing forward equity-minded school reforms while
also providing the means for doing so more effectively.
Overview
Welner uses a combination of statistical analyses and
case-study comparisons to examine the impact of equity-minded
reform, specifically desegregation and anti-tracking cases, in
four school districts. Welner defines “equity-minded
reform” as reform that seeks to change the fundamental
norms and beliefs of a community in order to re-distribute
resources to underserved members of the population. Welner
determines that legal action was a positive and necessary
component of the desegregation and anti-tracking reforms of the
districts he studied because such changes, at least initially,
require that the politically powerful be compelled to change
their practices.
Welner divides the book into three sections. Part I,
“Courting the Courts” (chapters 1-5), is a dense
section of the text. Here, Welner lays the legal and statistical
foundations for the book. He defines the terms of the book,
reviews the literature on tracking, reviews the legal and
community histories of four school districts wrestling with
desegregation and detracking, explains the court’s role in
education policy and administration generally and desegregation
legislation specifically, and presents various statistical
analyses concerning the state and effects of tracking in the four
school districts. Because of the detail and complexity of the
cases, it was difficult to absorb all the information in the
initial reading. The reader may need to return to this section
on occasion to refresh his or her memory on specific dates and
conclusions.
Part II, “Romancing the Zone”
(chapters 6-12), was the most compelling section of the book.
Welner sets forth his argument for how equity-minded reform
occurs, introduces the reader to his concept of the “zone
of mediation,” and describes the amount of detracking that
occurred in the school districts both with and without a
detracking mandate from the courts. He briefly and clearly
explains the terms and context of reform, sets these within the
existing literature, and then guides the reader through the
various forces that acted on the reform efforts with a wealth of
quotes that demonstrate both the practical and emotional
conflicts present.
If Part I was dense and Part II compelling, Part
III, “Making Mandates Matter” (chapters 13-15), was
mixed. In this section, Welner presents his evidence for the
extent of change that occurred in the school districts and makes
his case for a new vision of equity-minded reform and the role of
the courts therein. Welner’s evidence of court effected
change was thin, while his argument for the necessity of an
expanded vision of school reform and the court’s central
role in education reform was quite convincing.
It may be that Welner would have a stronger book if he had
stopped at a conceptual study of the role of law in school reform
rather than combining it with an empirical study. The next
sections will examine in more detail Welner’s conceptual
and empirical arguments for his conclusion that law is a
necessary component of equitable school reform. Interestingly,
the strengths and weaknesses of these arguments as presented in
Legal Rights, Local Wrongs parallel the trends and
tensions of this debate on legal advocacy for social change that
span the many disciplines that contribute to socio-legal
studies.
Conceptual Argument: Re-defining Education Reform
Welner contends that equity-minded reform involves four stages
“initiation, implementation, continuation and
outcome” (p. 236), but that too many reform initiatives
begin their focus on the implementation phase. As such, these
reform efforts attempt to change the technical aspects of
schooling—structure and resource allocation—while
often viewing schools and district organizations as neutral,
well-intentioned learning organizations who only need better
management to provide more equitable education. In reality,
Welner argues, schools and districts can be filled with
resistant, prejudiced players who work not for the American ideal
of equal opportunity, but the American practice of stratification
and protecting privilege. In these situations, equity-minded
reform must focus on socio-political change that emphasizes
changes in normative beliefs about race, intelligence and an
equitable society. With this focus, equity-minded reform must be
measured from the point of initiation, for even beginning reform
can be a tremendous accomplishment. Welner writes:
[I]n order to evaluate the overall, global efficacy of
different approaches to reforming schools, the analysis should
begin before the school, district, state, or federal
government has already inaugurated the reform. An initial
decision to embark upon a reform is, after all, a major hurdle,
and bottom-up change arises neither in a random fashion nor
necessarily in line with best practices. By focusing only on how
much of what was originally initiated or adopted is ultimately
implemented, the analyst overlooks the issue of the likelihood of
the reform actually being adopted in the first place. This
omission can be remedied by broadening the analysis to include
the universal (i.e., societal or nationwide) change likely to
result from the reform proposal. (p. 237, emphasis in
original)
Thus, one must begin an analysis of reform success by
determining the extent to which reform would occur voluntarily.
If a reform proposal were likely to meet widespread acceptance
and voluntary implementation, then the importance of the
initiation aspect of the reform would be secondary to successful
implementation. This type of reform analysis, starting at the
implementation phase, appears to be the standard view of
education reform. If, however, a reform proposal were likely to
meet considerable resistance, then Welner contends that a new
approach is necessary. In this case, the success of the
reformers at simply creating the context for change (initiation
phase) should be given equal or greater consideration than what
occurs at the implementation phase when determining the level of
success achieved.
Welner uses a concept he calls the “zone of
mediation.” (2001, p. 94) to explain the importance of
initiating the process of change involved in equity-minded
reforms. The zone of mediation is “the boundaries of
debate for a given issue” formed from all the “larger
cultural norms, rules, incentives, power relations and
values” of a particular context. (2001, p. 95) Welner
concludes that equity-minded school reforms, like detracking,
seek to redefine fundamental aspects of the zone of mediation and
thus activate the power of entrenched interest groups from
teachers to parents to district personnel who will attempt to
maintain the unequal status quo. This type of change is
“third-order change” because it goes beyond changing
the technical aspects of current teaching practice (first-order
change) and the basic ways that schools function as organizations
(second-order change) to change “educators’ and
community members’ core normative beliefs about such
matters as race, class, intelligence, and educability.”
(2001, p. 239)
In third-order change situations, Welner contends that success
should be measured from initiation because merely creating a
receptive zone of mediation is difficult. Minority populations,
by definition, will need top-down mandates, like court orders, to
overcome the majority’s core beliefs that support the
current inequitable structures. Thus, he concludes, school
reformers should embrace top-down mandates for equity-minded
reforms for they provide some essential tools for change and they
should recognize this as an important step in the reform effort.
Nevertheless, Welner reminds the reader that top-down mandates
while necessary, are not sufficient to effect substantive,
lasting change, and must be combined with additional forces to
alter the political, normative, structural and technical aspects
of the social context.
Welner makes a forceful case. His reform model is in keeping
with the role of the courts in U.S. democracy. The Supreme Court
in Marburyv. Madison, 2 L. Ed. 60 (1803),
recognized that minority groups must be protected from the
tyranny of the majority in certain fundamental areas, like
segregation. As such, the courts have and should dictate social
policy (Heubert, 1999; Feeley & Rubin, 1998) in order to
enable members of minority groups to assert their rights
sufficiently to create a zone of mediation that is receptive to
equitable reform.
Empirical Study: Measuring reform
Welner gets bogged down, however, in his attempts to measure
the extent of reform that results from the court mandates to
detrack. The data were difficult to follow and, at times,
unconvincing. Welner sets out to do a comparative analysis of
change processes in four school districts “struggling with
racial equality and school reform” (2001, p. 4), but
focused his attention on one school district, Woodland Hills,
Pennsylvania. The data was collected by a team of researchers
over several years, though it is not clear from the text exactly
how many. Welner participated in the data collection process in
three of the four districts, including Woodland Hills. Welner
conducted his specific research on the Woodland Hills district
during “four, week-long visits during the 1996-1997 school
year.” (2001, p. 270, note 8) During these four weeks,
Welner collected documents, observed classes, and
“completed more than 90 interviews.” (Ibid)
In reading this, it becomes hard to imagine that any
observations or interviews of depth could be uncovered by
conducting so many in so short a period of time. This amount of
time did not seem sufficient to create the “thick
descriptions” that mark the foundation of this type of
qualitative research (van Manen, 1990). As such, it was
difficult to conclude that Welner was uncovering the subtle,
underlying aspects of school life in Woodland Hills, aspects that
were outside the conscious awareness or unconscious deception
(Erickson, 1986) of the participants he interviewed or
observed.
Even with this concern, Welner’s presentation of the
current perceptions of the members of the Woodland Hills school
district was quite strong. Welner ties together numerous quotes
to bring to life how the various forces operated on the zone of
mediation of detracking. A representative example quotes a
veteran teacher’s view of the detracking reforms:
I’ve been teaching [for about 30 years, and I’m
not going to] begin to start something brand new. . . .I’ve
gone through all the different changes and have tried all the
changes. You end up doing what you feel is best for you. (p.
111)
Other, openly racist remarks, are rarely spoken aloud, so they
made quite an impression when presented in the text. Examples
include teachers saying that the difficulties of teaching in
heterogeneous classes makes them “‘hate’ the
students” (p. 138) and that “it’s unbelievable.
. . the [low] intelligence, the capabilities of the [Black]
students now” (p. 175), while an administrator described
the strategy of some White parents,
I will gut out the first 6 years of elementary school, where
my child’s in a classroom with Black kids. I’ll gut
that out because I know when I get to junior high and senior high
my kid, through core scheduling or whatever, can get away from
those kids. (p. 195)
These quotes provide a visceral quality to the emotional
obstacles in equitable reform.
Despite the hard-hitting quotes demonstrating the racist
resistance to reform, Welner never loses sight of its
complexities. Welner quotes both White and Black parents who
viewed the African-American culture as impeding the academic
success of Black students. Welner also notes that teacher
resistance to change was based not only on racism, but also anger
at being the scapegoats for the inequities of U.S. society. In
this sense, teachers appear both as victims and victimizers. As
one teacher “angrily declared, ‘We resent when people
come in and say, ‘if you can’t figure this out,
you’re no good.’ Agreed another, ‘if you
can’t do a good job of teaching this incredible spectrum,
then inherently you’re a poor teacher.’” (p.
141) Overall, Welner’s quotations provide a vivid
description of the reasoned intentions of people wrestling with
and against the equitable reform of detracking.
Welner’s attempt to then measure the extent of
reform presents several difficulties. Welner tries to assess
change over time, but he does not compare like data. Initially,
Welner uses a variety of statistical analyses to demonstrate the
level and effect of tracking on the four specific school
districts studied. From these, he determines that the tracking
in all four school districts resulted in minority students being
place disproportionately in low-tracked classes; that these
tracks encompassed a wide range of measured abilities; that
students who qualified for two more tracks were treated
differently based on race—students of color were more often
placed in the lower tracks while white students were more often
placed in the higher tracks; that students had to overcome great
odds to move up within the tracked structure; and that each year
the low-tracked students fell farther behind their high-tracked
counterparts. To this, Welner added the qualitative
data—interviews, news articles, classroom observations and
the non-statistical parts of district documents—to describe
the change in the larger societal context over time. From all
this, Welner determines that the three districts under court
mandates made progress toward more equitable, detracked
schooling. Focusing on Woodland Hills, he concludes that
[i]n the wake of the Woodland Hills court order, the
district’s schools experienced substantial change in at
least five areas: detracking and classroom desegregation,
expectations for student achievement, instructional methods, the
written curriculum, and supplemental and supportive programs.
But the change in all these areas was less than that intended or
desired by the court and by others pushing for reform. (p.
216)
In making these conclusions, Welner appears to be comparing
the individual statements of persons from Woodland Hills with the
results of the earlier statistical analyses, which is problematic
in two ways. First, in Chapter 4, Welner presents a wealth of
tables on the tracking placements and their potential impact in
the four districts. Of the 25 tables and graphs, 11 concerned
Woodland Hills. Of these 11, none appear to present the level of
tracking and its effect on students achievement and opportunity
prior to the court-supervised consent decree of 1988 or the
detracking agreement of 1994. The first graph, figure 4.1 is
undated and the remaining ten graphs and tables concern the years
1995-1997. Thus, it is unclear what Welner is using for his
initial baseline against which he can measure improvement.
Second, in Chapter 13, he presents the final 1997 state of
desegregation and detracking in Woodland Hills. Here, the data
are short, qualified descriptions about the actual, not merely
nominal, extent of the social studies, math and science
detracking (all, some and none, respectively) followed by more
extensive second-hand statements about teacher attitude and
individual student performance in the detracked English classes.
It is unclear whether these statements are intended to reflect
the teachers’ perceptions about change that has occurred as
a result of the court mandated reforms or are being used as a
comparison to the quantitative data analyses presented earlier.
Either way, neither appear to be sufficient to measure the extent
of actual progress in program reform.
Similar empirical questions exist in Welner’s assessment
regarding the changes in instructional methods. First, Welner
does not provide any direct evidence of the pre-court mandate
instructional methods. Second, Welner’s evidence of the
final 1997 state of the instructional methods at Woodland Hills
is largely second-hand and anecdotal. Most of the evidence
consists of statements like “one principal observed”
(p. 208) about certain teachers or “a junior high teacher
English teacher explained” (p. 209) about herself. When
Welner makes his own observations, they appear to demonstrate a
lack of knowledge about progressive pedagogy. On page 208, for
example, Welner, in describing teachers who “designed
lessons intended to challenge all students” wrote about a
teacher who “seemed constantly aware of each
student’s needs.” She did this by asking the
students to write a paragraph emphasizing “action
verbs” and then asking a student who finished early,
“Can I challenge you?” Yes, this may be progress in
Woodland Hills, but it is hardly indicative of the current
knowledge or practice of progressive teaching methods for either
tracked or heterogeneous classes (e.g., Shor & Pari,
1999). Welner neither provides baseline data for the reader to
make his or her own conclusion about the extent of change in
instructional methods nor comments about his own awareness of the
lack of innovation in the examples. This may leave the reader
less convinced than Welner in the “substantial
change” resulting from the court-mandated detracking.
In attempting to measure the effect of court mandated social
reform, Welner is taking on a daunting task. Socio-legal
scholars have been wrestling with this for decades. On one end
of the spectrum, Michael McCann in Rights at Work (1994)
uses qualitative methods and concludes that law is effective in
creating equity minded reform. McCann’s findings parallel
those of Welner. McCann finds law to be most significant during
the movement building and transformation phases of social
movement struggle. Commenting on the transformation phase,
McCann found evidence that “perhaps the single most
important achievement of the movements has been the
transformations in many working women’s [and other
workers’] understandings, commitments, and
affiliations—i.e., in their hearts, minds, and social
identities.” (1994, p. 230) In other words, the process
itself educated and empowered those involved. The movement
building and transformation phases are quite similar to
Welner’s initiation phase and his emphasis on changing
normative beliefs. In the end, McCann argues that “[l]aw
works variably both as a resource and as a constraint in
practical activity” (1994, p. 283); that legal victories,
while neither necessary nor sufficient for change, can
contribute; and that due to the “overwhelming systematic
inequalities and scarcities in basic resources that oppress
subordinate groups, even limited, contingent, uncertain resources
such as our legal traditions offer should be appreciated.”
(1994, p. 309) This again is consistent with Welner’s
conclusions about the role of law in education reform.
At the other end of the spectrum, Gerald Rosenberg uses mostly
quantitative methods and concludes that law does not promote
socially equitable reform, except in concert with other political
and economic forces. In Hollow Hope (1991), Rosenberg
examines “liberal” decisions of the Supreme Court to
study whether courts can and do produce social change. Using
civil rights and Brown v. Board of Education, 347
U.S. 483 (1954) as an example, Rosenberg found no direct judicial
effects, concluding that the courts were ineffective in producing
significant changes in civil rights until the federal government
supported the civil rights movement by providing financial
incentives for compliance. “Courts can matter, but only
sometimes, and only under limited conditions.” (1991, p.
106) In many ways, Rosenburg concludes that law and the courts
“provide only an illusion of change.” (1991, p.
341) This contradicted Welner’s conclusions.
Rosenburg’s analysis focuses on the implementation phase
of a social movement and mostly on quantifiable, statistical
measures like the racial mix of a classroom and less on the
change in perception of individual participants. Following
Welner’s reconceptualization of reform movements, the
implementation phase would be the least likely area of success in
equity-minded reform and the use of statistics and quantitative
analysis alone would not fully describe the extent of reform
achieved. Perhaps, Rosenberg finds no change because he is
trying to measure what statistics are not best suited to measure
(McCann, 1996).
Taking Welner, McCann and Rosenburg’s analysis together
might explain the strengths and weaknesses not only of Legal
Rights and Local Wrongs, but also the current state of
socio-legal research on the role of law and courts in equitable
social reform. There is no consensus yet on what should be
studied or on what evidence should change be understood or
measured (Rosenberg, 1996; McCann, 1996). When Welner, like
McCann, uses qualitative methods to understand changes in
normative beliefs, his work is compelling. When, in contrast to
Rosenberg, he uses quantitative or mixed methods to demonstrate
that positive changes in implementation have occurred, his work
is unpersuasive; perhaps, in part, because he may be attempting
to measure what is currently unmeasurable—direct judicial
effects.
Conclusion
Overall, Legal Rights and Local Wrongs has much to
offer educational reformers. Welner states early and often that
legal means should be used for equitable social change,
specifically equitable education reform. Welner reminds readers
that the role of the courts in a constitutional democracy is to
protect certain fundamental rights from the tyranny of majority
rule. Commenting on how to understand the impact of law and
legal actions on reform, Welner asserts convincingly that changes
in the consciousness of the community should be given greater
emphasis.
Welner’s work has one major drawback which is currently
a tension in socio-legal studies. In using both quantitative and
qualitative methods, he cannot seem to separate causation from
resonant understanding. He must choose whether he wants to argue
causation and then measure change over time with a quantitative,
statistical analysis or argue resonant value of a case study and
then use a descriptive analysis. This is the debate between
McCann and Rosenberg and, in essence, all socio-legal studies
that has yet to be resolved by researchers.
Welner tries to do both which is too much. His sections
arguing for the use of the courts in spearheading equity-minded
reform that should be measured from initiation and not just
implementation are clear and well-reasoned, and his qualitative
sections that focus on the perceptions of the various
participants support his contentions. It is when Welner attempts
to measure the direct extent to which the courts caused the
implementation of detracking that his methods and evidence are
less convincing.
Welner’s call to confront equity-minded reform as
necessary for just educational opportunity and to do so openly is
important in this time when the popular debate appears to be
dominated by those promoting market-theories as a painless,
profitable and neutral means to achieve public goods like quality
education for every student. And, Welner’s conclusions
that the courts should and must take an active role in this
reform process is also important to hear at a time when court
actions that defend minority rights are too often disparaged as
judicial activism. I would recommend Legal Rights and Local
Wrongs to reform-minded educators and socio-legal scholars
with enough knowledge of education policy and the role of law in
social reform to see both its empirical limitations and
conceptual strengths.
References
Erickson, F. (1986). “Qualitative methods in research on
teaching.” In Wittrock, M. (Ed.), Handbook of research
on teaching, 3rd ed. (pp. 119-161). New
York: Macmillan Publishing Company.
Feeley, M. & Rubin, E. (1998). Judicial policy making
and the modern state: How the courts reformed America’s
prisons. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Heubert, J. (1999). Law and school reform: Six strategies
for promoting educational equity. New Haven, CN: Yale
University Press.
McCann, M. (1994). Rights at work: Pay equity reform and
the politics of legal mobilization. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
McCann, M. (1996). “Causal versus constitutive
explanations (or, on the difficulty of being so positive . .
.).”Law and Social Inquiry, vol. 21 no. 2, pp.
457-482.
Rosenberg, G. (1991). The hollow hope: Can courts bring
about social change. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Rosenberg, G. (1996). “Positivism, interpretivism, and
the study of law.” Law and Social Inquiry, vol. 21
no. 2, pp. 435-455.
Shor, I. & Pari, C. (1999). Education is politics:
Critical teaching across differences, K-12. Portsmouth, NH:
Heinemann.
van Manen, M. (1990). Researching lived experience.
Ontario: State University of New York Press.
About the Reviewer
Eric Haas
College of Education
Arizona State University
Tempe, AZ 85287-2411
Email: eric.haas@asu.edu
Eric Haas is a lawyer, former middle teacher, and doctoral
student in education policy at Arizona State University. His
research interests include education law and the media
presentation of education issues.
[ home |
overview | reviews | editors | submit | guidelines | announcements ]
| |