|
This review has been accessed times since November 11, 2003
Apple, Michael W. (2001). Educating the “Right”
Way: Markets, Standards, God, and Inequality. New York and
London: Routledge/Falmer.
Pp. 306
$23.95 (paper) ISBN 0-145-92462-6
Reviewed by Ramin Farahmandpur
Portland State University
November 11, 2003
For the past two decades, one of the major undertakings of
critical educational theorist Michael Apple has been to study the
causes of the rise of the New Right and its impact on
educational policies in the United States. Educating the
“Right” Way: Markets, Standards, God, and
Inequality can be described as a sequel to his two previously
published books: Official Knowledge: Democratic Education in a
Conservative Age (1993) and Education and Cultural
Politics (1996), in which Apple explored the resurgence of
the conservative restoration in the United States. In his most
recent work, Apple examines how the social, political, economic,
and cultural movements on the right have succeeded in forming a
"hegemonic alliance" in order to influence and shape
educational policies in the United States.
In chapters one and two, Apple identifies four major social,
political, and ideological movements, which he refers to as the
"hegemonic alliance of the New Right." These four
movements include: neoliberals, neoconservatives,
authoritarian populists, and the new middle class.
Apple suggests that although each movement has different and
oftentimes conflicting political and ideological interests, they
form a "hegemonic alliance" when it comes to
opposing progressive and democratic forces on the Left. In a
concerted effort to advance its social, economic, political, and
ideological agenda, Apple claims that the New Right exercises
hegemony primarily through the medium of ideological leadership.
He explains that the New Right’s tactics include, for
example, the use of key concepts such as markets,
standards, God, and inequality. Each concept
constitutes one of the central tenets of the social movements
within the New Right. For instance, neoliberals are proponents of
the market; neoconservatives are determined to enforce
traditional curriculum and national standards across the
country; authoritarian populists are motivated by a desire to
integrate religion and God within the school curriculum;
and finally, the new middle class and the professional managerial
class are associated with maintaining social and economic
inequality by supporting educational policies that are
favorable to their class standing within society.
In his analysis of the causes of the rise of the
"conservative alliance," Apple draws upon
Gramsci’s concept of the "commonsense." Apple
generally limits the "commonsense" to ideological
struggles and defines it as the "basic categories"
or "key words" such as "democracy,"
"freedom," and "equality" that are used
by people to make sense of the social world. He attributes the
rise of the New Right to its cunning ability to change or
"alter" the meaning of the commonly held beliefs and
views of people of the social world. (Note 1) Apple believes that the New Right
success in changing people’s commonsense is due to its use
of a "simple" language that people can understand.
He refers to this strategy as "plain speaking."
In chapter three, Apple examines the hegemonic alliances
among the forces on the Right and the Left. He identified these
alliances as a “decentered unity,” a concept whose
origin can be traced back to the "radical democratic"
approach of post-Marxists Ernesto Laclau and Chantal Mouffe
(1985). (Note 2) Apple
explains that the "decentered unity" consists of a
constellation of progressive social groups that form a
counter-hegemonic alliance against the
dominant social groups in society (i.e., the New Right). In
contrast to the Leninist strategy of "democratic
centrism," in which the vanguard party operated as the
"ideological and political compass" of the
proletariat, Apple firmly espouses the notion of a
"decentered unity" that consists of an alliance among
feminists, multiculturalists, lesbians, gays, anti-racists,
environmentalists, peace activists, progressives, and
neo-Marxists. (Note 3) Apple
describes the "decentered unity" as an alliance that
encompasses a broad range of progressive forces and social
groups. Hence, he maintains that the "decentered
unity" does not succumb to an "official"
centralized bureaucratic party line because it is inclusive of
multiple voices and subject positions.
In chapters four and five, Apple takes a closer look at the
ideology behind the authoritarian populist religious conservative
movement. Apple offers both a historical and a political
overview of one of the most hotly debated controversies that has
erupted over the years in public schools, namely, the teaching of
evolutionary science. Apple provides a number of examples
including one state school board in Alabama that required all
biology textbooks adopted by the state to have a disclaimer
noting that evolutionary science is one of the many theories
explaining the development of human life. Apple also shows how
politicians such as Ronald Reagan and Pat Buchanan have been
instrumental in supporting the causes of the religious Right
by denouncing Darwinism and evolutionary science. In chapter
five, Apple also shows how evangelicals and Christians on the
Right of the political spectrum, including Pat Robertson and
Ralph Reed, have been major political and ideological forces in
influencing the course and the direction of educational policies
at the local, state, and national levels. One example involves
the controversy over school prayers in public schools.
In chapter six, Apple examines the growing trend of
homeschooling in the context of the current social, political,
cultural, and economic climate. He notes that while not all
parents who homeschool their children hold conservative
religious viewpoints, most have a biblical interpretation of the
family unit, maintain non-secular views on gender dynamics, and
have their own views on what counts as "legitimate
knowledge." Apple is alarmed with the homeschooling
movement because he believes it is leading to the
"suburbanization of everyday life" and the
"segmentation of American society." Here, he is
referring to the increasing race, class, and gender divisions in
American society. Apple is equally concerned about the
contradictory nature of educational policies that allows public
money for creating charter schools be used by homeschoolers to
teach religious viewpoints that would otherwise violate the
separation of church and state in the constitution. Apple
believes that these loopholes in the federal and state
educational policies privileges students from religious
segments of society over students from economically
disadvantaged backgrounds.
Chapter seven includes perhaps the most contentious facet of
Apple’s concept of "decentered unity." In this
chapter, Apple puts forth a "dual strategy" approach
for building counter-hegemonic alliances. Apple’s dual
strategy approach consists of progressive and
tactical alliances. Progressive alliances are those
that are forged among progressive forces, which include
anti-globalization activists, peace organizers,
environmentalists, feminists, the working class, and gays and
lesbians. On the other hand, Apple explains that tactical
alliances are those that can be developed among progressive
forces and factions from within the Right wing. For example,
Apple proposes that it is possible to make tactical alliances
with the anti-corporatist sentiments of authoritarian populists
on the Right. The reasoning behind this type alliance is based
entirely on common ideological interests. For example, he notes
that both the populist Right and the Left have been strong
opponents of Chris Whittle’s Channel One. By the same
token, Apple is optimistic that tactical alliances can be forged
with the populist Right on controversial issues such as state
curricula and testing. Of course, this is not to suggest that
Apple does not recognize that these alliances need to be
approached with extreme caution.
While I agree with Apple’s deep-seated social and
political convictions, and concur with his criticism of the New
Right’s attempt to shape the course of educational
policies in the United States, I remain skeptical regarding his
theoretical framework, in particular his neo-Marxist approach to
educational reform on a number of major points. These include,
among others, his neo-Marxist interpretation of Gramsci’s
concept of the “commonsense”; his use of the
“decentered unity,” which he identifies as an
counter-hegemonic alliance among progressive forces on the left;
and finally, his notion of a “dual strategy” for
building alliances between progressive forces on the left and
those on the Right.
First, there is no doubt that Gramsci’s concept of
commonsense is an improvement over Marx and Engels’
interpretations of ideology as “false consciousness.”
Yet, to their credit, Marx and Engels were wholly aware that the
concept of ideology, which they interpreted as
“false consciousness,” did not simply express a
false outlook or a "simple inversion" of the social
world that the ruling classes imposed on the masses.
Consequently, Apple’s claim that the New Right’s
success in changing our commonsense is achieved simply by
redefining those key ideas (i.e., equality, freedom, democracy)
on its own turf is not entirely convincing. Hegemony cannot be
achieved simply by means of discursive practices or by way of a
"war of position" alone. Stated differently, in their
struggles to build alliances by winning over the masses, the
Right and the Left do not merely engage in what Gramsci referred
to as the "war of position," but also in a "war
of maneuver." (Note 4)
Apple believes that the task of the counter-hegemonic
alliances among the progressive forces is to develop
"creative ways" or measures to win over the masses.
In other words, the educational Left should emulate the
Right’s success by providing the popular masses an
alternative progressive discourse that redefines those key
"concepts" (i.e., democracy, freedom, and equality).
However, in doing so, Apple falls into "theoretical
voluntarism." This is because he underestimates the
intimate relationship between ideology and the “material
structural determinations” (Mészáros, 1989).
Given the fact that the anti-capitalist movements must overcome
overwhelming “material constraints,” there is no
symmetrical distance in the relationship between “critical
ideology” and “established ideology” to the
commonsense of the people (Mészáros, 1989).
Furthermore, Apple holds that ideological dispositions do not
necessarily correspond to economic, political, or cultural
positions of individuals or groups of people. He claims that
ideology, class, politics, and culture are "relatively
autonomous" from one another. However, his explanation
offers little, if any, insight into “how ideologies become
a part of the popular consciousness of classes and class
fractions who are not among the elite” (Meiksins Wood,
1986, p. 16). The reason why Apple attributes the rise of the New
Right to its ability to alter the meaning of concepts such as
"democracy" and "freedom" is because he
severs ideological contradictions from class antagonisms. Absent
from Apple’s neo-Marxist approach to educational reform is
any sustained effort to examine class antagonisms among the
subordinate groups and the dominant groups. Subsequently, Apple
is stranded in a form of "radical idealism." This is
because people’s commonsense is shaped not only by the
alteration of the meaning of key concepts like
"democracy" and "freedom" but also by the
class struggles between the capitalist class and the working
class.
Finally, Apple’s understanding of the concept of
commonsense is limited because it is not sufficiently grounded
within the material practices and activities of men and women.
There are other pressing questions that remain unanswered. Some
of these include: What is the relationship between good sense and
bad sense? How are truth and misrepresentations related to one
another? What is the composition of the commonsense? Are there
more elements of bad sense than good sense? In short,
Apple’s employment of the "commonsense" fails
to explain, in the main, how and why people’s misperception
of the world occurs the way that it does.
Second, I find Apple’s notion of the
"decentered unity" highly problematic for a number of
reasons. To begin with, one of the questions is: what holds the
"decentered unity" together? Stated differently: What
is the ideological bond that unites these diverse groups of
differing social, political, and economic interests? Apple is
quick to acknowledge this dilemma. He admits that there are
“real differences” among the wide spectrum of social
and political groups that include, for example, political,
epistemological, and educational differences. If this is the
case, then the follow-up question is: What are the ideological or
political forces that conjoins these diverse groups? Responding
to these criticisms, Apple writes that the "decentered
unity" is “united in [its] opposition to the forces
involved in the new conservative hegemonic alliance” (p.
96). However, Apple’s reply does not sufficiently justify
such a loosely knitted coalition.
For example, Apple derives the identity of the new social
movements from their immediate experiences with oppression. Yet,
in his polemic against E. P. Thompson, Perry Anderson (1980)
reminds us that experiences alone do not guarantee agency.
In other words, there is no assurance that experiences arising
from a particular form of oppression will generate progressive
forms of social action, or motivate a class, for example, to
organize itself and rise up against social injustices. Anderson
(1980) raises a number of other fundamental questions that are no
less important. These include: How can we distinguish between a
valid and invalid experience? And are religious experiences
valid?
Apple further notes that the New Right’s success is
largely due to its ability to build a "decentered
unity." Consequently, he recommends that the Left and
progressive forces should learn from the victories of the New
Right in their effort to build a progressive "decentered
unity." On this point, Apple notes: “The right has
been much more successful …than the left, in part because
it has been able to craft—through hard and lengthy
economic, political, and cultural efforts—a tense but still
successful alliance that has shifted the major debates over
education and economic and social policy onto its on
terrain.”(p. 195). However, one of the underlying
weaknesses in Apple’s strategy is that he juxtaposes the
hegemonic and counter-hegemonic alliances among the forces of the
Right and the Left. In Apple’s view, the Right and the
Left are involved in a battle to persuade the masses to join
their social and political cause. Hence, Apple leaves us with a
political project that reduces social struggles to ideological
battles between the Right and the Left that are largely fought in
the terrain of discourse and language.
Finally, in response to Apple’s proposal for a dual
strategy, which consists of progressive and tactical alliances,
the question I raise is whether it is feasible to develop
alliances with factions of the New Right. Can the Right and the
Left articulate mutual interests against corporations purely on
common ideological interests? To Answer this question we need to
take a step back and revisit Laclau and Mouffe’s (1985)
notion of radical democracy and their unconditional endorsement
of the new social movements. For Laclau and Mouffe (1985), the
primary contradictions within capitalist social relations of
production are not limited to class antagonisms alone, but
also extend to ideological and political contradictions. By
agreeing with Laclau and Mouffe (1985), who proclaim that
political identity is not reducible to class identity, and who
also endorse the premise of the irreducibility of ideological and
cultural conflicts to class interests, Apple can claim that
ideological and cultural struggles enjoy some measure of
autonomy from class struggles. And by claiming that ideology and
culture are relatively autonomous from class relations, it is
clear why Apple believes that the New Right can simply alter the
meaning of key concepts such as "democracy,"
"freedom," and "equality" to serve its
own social, economic, and political interests. Cloaked in a
poststructuralist reading of hegemony, Apple simply reduces
socialist struggle to an ideological warfare between the Left and
the Right.
In spite of my critical review of his book, there is no
question that over the years Michael Apple has made important
scholarly contributions to the field of educational theory and
practice. For the past three decades, Apple has not only proven
to be one of the most vocal critics of the New Right, but he has
also a tireless activist in the North American radical
educational scene, not to mention a prominent scholar within
international circles. Nonetheless, I believe that Apple’s
neo-Marxist disposition in rebuilding alliances and coalitions
remains both theoretically and practically problematic for
organizing and developing a coherent anti-capitalist social and
political movement among the educational left.
Notes
1. There are,
however, a number of inconsistencies in Apple’s arguments.
For example, there are moments when Apple reduces social
struggles to mere ideological struggles, and there are other
moments when ideological struggles take precedence over class
struggles.
2. One definition
of the term is, “to undermine the usual hierarchy of a
dominant system by showing that its center may hold only a
relative, not a fixed point, or that the center may be exchanged
with a place on the margins.”
3. One of the
major flaws associated with Michael Apple’s distinction
between moral and intellectual leadership and political
domination is that he rejects the important role the vanguard
party plays in seizing political power. To establish "the
dictatorship of the proletariat," the working-class must
seize state power. However, Apple’s claims that the ruling
classes (in Apple’s case, the New Right) establishes
domination by means of moral and intellectual leadership alone.
For Apple, hegemony connotes moral and intellectual leadership.
In addition, moral and intellectual leadership precedes political
dominance. Overall, Apple’s objective is to deny the
importance of the vanguard party.
4. Here, I am
using the term “war of maneuver" to mean class
struggle.
References
Apple, M. W. (1993). Official knowledge: Democratic
education in a conservative age. New York: Routledge &
Kegan Paul.
Apple, M. W. (1996). Education and cultural politics.
New York: Teachers College Press.
Laclau, E., and Mouffe, C. (1985). Hegemony and socialist
strategy: Toward a radical democratic politics. London and
New York: Verso.
Mészáros, I. (1989). The power of ideology.
New York: New York University Press.
Wood, E. M. (1986). The retreat from class: A new 'true'
socialism. London and New York: Verso classics.
About the Reviewer
Ramin Farahmandpur is an assistant professor in the
Department of Educational Policy, Foundations and Administrative
Studies at Portland State University. He recently completed his
Ph.D. in the field of Curriculum Theory and Teaching Studies from
the Graduate School of Education and Informational Studies at
UCLA. His work has appeared in Educational Researcher,
Journal of Teacher Education, Journal of Curriculum
Theorizing, Educational Policy, and Multicultural
Education. His current interests include Marxist educational
theory, critical pedagogy, and multicultural education.
~
ER home |
Reseņas Educativas |
Resenhas Educativas ~
~
overview | reviews | editors | submit | guidelines | announcements
~
| |