|
This review has been accessed times since April 24, 2004
Parker, Walter C. (2003). Teaching democracy: Unity and
diversity in public life. New York: Teachers College
Press
Pp. xxiii + 191
$25.95 ISBN 0-8077-4272-4
Reviewed by Becky Ropers-Huilman
Louisiana State University
April 24, 2004
There is perhaps no more pressing problem in the world today
than how to teach diverse individuals and groups to live and work
together with mutual support and benefit. With increasing
globalization, continuing population shifts, and changing
environmental and social needs, it is crucial that citizens
engage in the participatory self-governance that is often termed
“democracy.” Walter C. Parker’s text on
Teaching democracy explores how “enlightened
political engagement” can be fostered in democratic
societies, paying particular attention to both the potential and
limitations of educational institutions in the United States.
Throughout the text, Parker argues that “Schools are ideal
places to educate citizens for democratic living in a diverse
society” (p. 160). Couching this assertion within
historical events and understandings, his message is particularly
compelling.
Essential to his thematic development, Parker first frames his
work around the need to move from “idiocy” to
“citizenship.” He argues that idiocy refers to a
self-centered individual who is not concerned with, and
essentially ignores, public engagement. He further defines idiocy
as “self- and familial-indulgence at the expense of the
common good” (p. 33). Referring to the contributions of
Alexis de Tocqueville (1848/1969), Parker suggests that
“idiots are idiotic precisely because they are indifferent
to the conditions and contexts of their own freedom” (p.
4). This self-serving approach limits the effectiveness of both
government and communities, and has substantially negative
results for both those involved in decision-making processes, as
well as those who are not.
Parker strongly advocates that our society and
world will benefit from a move from idiocy to engaged citizenry,
and that schools have a key role to play in this transition. In
formulating his argument, he suggests that three guiding ideas
can help educators and other community members alike live as
democratic citizens through enlightened political engagement.
Specifically, he poses the concepts of path, participation, and
pluralism. By “path,” Parker means to indicate that
democracy is not something that is accomplished or attained.
Rather, it is a process – a path – of continued and
deepening engagement that yields benefits to those who walk it,
as well as to the communities to which they contribute. By
“participation,” Parker suggests that democratic
citizens must do more than think about the ways that they could
make their lives and communities better. Indeed, their
participation goes beyond accepting alternatives presented by
others and, perhaps, voting on those alternatives. Instead,
democratic citizens participate fully in the creation of
alternatives, solutions, and processes through which to
self-govern. Finally, with the term “pluralism,”
Parker puts forth that diversity is a necessary part of liberty
and nurtures democracy. As this last point is particularly
prevalent in Parker’s work, I turn now to a more focused
examination of that idea.
Throughout this text, Parker asserts that
democracy and diversity rely on and strengthen each other.
Indeed, as Parker writes, “Democratic citizenship education
seeks to teach, among other things, that diversity is a
social fact, that it is a social good, why this is
so, and how diversity and democracy require one
another” (p. 1). Powerfully using quotes from and concepts
embraced by Martin Luther King, Jr., he suggests that
interpersonal relations at both the individual and community
levels must be considered in all their diversity if a democracy
is to move toward its ideal form. Specifically, he writes,
“To seek virtue and social justice is to understand that
the individual and the community must be known
simultaneously” (p. 75). Problems that may arise from these
attempts to understand others (both in the individual and
community sense) can be framed not as stumbling blocks, but
rather as essential elements that foster important dialogue and
deliberation in democracies. Through engagement in active
deliberation, all are able to – and have a responsibility
to – contribute to understandings and solutions that are
generated.
At the same time, Parker asserts, it must be
acknowledged that actors come to deliberative dialogue with
different relationships to privilege. Both those with greater
access to privilege in a given community, and those with less
access, benefit from democratic education, as all stand to gain
deeper understandings of the communities in which they live.
Still, it is important to note, “Difference is not only a
social fact but a political fact, because power is
involved” (p. 160). Democratic interactions must
consciously be aware of they ways that power and privilege affect
their interactions, identification of problems, processes, and
solutions. Indeed, Parker indicates, at times social groups may
wish to consciously privilege people who are situated in
particular ways, as those people (having “insider
knowledge” or “epistemic privilege”) may be
particularly well suited to contribute perspectives that are
essential to the solving of community problems.
Parker does not limit his work to how democratic
engagement can be fostered in schools. Instead, a key strength of
this text is that he draws from his knowledge of interactions
outside of schools, both to illustrate how out-of-school (or
out-of-class) interactions can be important to democratic
development, as well as to draw ideas from other contexts into
schools to explore how they can be used to reach students in more
formal settings. As one example of how out-of-school experiences
can foster learning toward citizenship, he discusses what
involvement in voluntary associations teaches its participants.
Specifically, he suggests that such involvement helps one learn
about pluralism, through an expansion of the types of people and
perspectives that one comes into contact with. That expansion, he
argues, allows one to understand community problems, rather than
problems that are only immediately apparent in one’s own
individual or familial situation. Through deliberation about
community problems, Parker believes that better understandings of
diverse others will be developed, as well as better solutions to
common problems.
Turning more directly to schools, Parker argues
that while mere school attendance has been shown to be
significant in fostering political engagement, it is imperative
that educators think deliberately about their practices to ensure
that they are proactively working to educate citizens in their
communities. In his argument, he draws on Cherryholmes (1980) to
explain that what has been termed “citizenship
education” can be classified as either critical or
non-critical, helping students to either actively participate in
existing structures (non-critical) or to actively shape
democratic dialogue about how existing structures embrace certain
problems and solutions at the expense of others (critical). From
these approaches has arisen a tension between approaches that
emphasize participation, and those that emphasize transmission.
In other words, some believe that in order for schools to
effectively help students learn how to be democratic actors, they
must themselves be arranged democratically. In this way, students
can learn through participation in one of their primary social
settings about how to be enlightened political actors. On the
other hand, some believe that schools’ primary role in
citizenship education must be the transmission of knowledge about
how democracy was formed, how it is enacted today, and why it
might be important to become a democratic participant. Notably,
Parker argues that these approaches can be enacted in
complementary ways, but that educators must consciously work to
do this, rather than hope that either knowledge or skills will be
somehow absorbed without conscious and focused pedagogical
efforts.
Another dimension of the tension Parker
articulates between participation and transmission in schools is
further explored in a discussion of two groups of those
explicitly working to promote social justice: those oriented to
promote engagement and those oriented to promote enlightenment.
In this text, the reader can see the parallels between justice
and democratic engagement through the tensions associate with
participation/transmission and engagement/enlightenment. While
this connection is clearly important to explore, it is perhaps
Parker’s insistence on the role of justice in democratic
education that is most significant. Specifically, he writes,
“We should not overlook the fact that deploying either [the
engagement or enlightenment perspective] presupposes that we have
grappled with the meaning of justice, that we ourselves
have attempted to think it through, that we have searched for a
personal understanding of what it means to do the right
thing” (p. 55). In this way, Parker asks educators to
actively engage with the knowledge and action that they are
attempting to value in their interactions with students. He
implicitly poses the questions: If we value democratic
citizenship enough to prioritize it in our schools,
shouldn’t we each, as educators, value it – and
practice it – in our lives? And, if so, shouldn’t we
do so in as “just” and moral way as possible? These
bold questions are not often framed so poignantly in academic
literature, and they urge readers to seriously consider the roles
that they play, not just as teachers or administrators, but also
as democratic citizens who may or may not be involved in
enlightened political engagement.
The latter part of the book turns to a discussion
of concrete practices and ideas that educators may wish to
implement to engage with the concepts offered earlier in the
text. While these suggestions range from concrete and specific to
the more abstract, and from elementary school through secondary
schools, they are guided by the principles Parker associates with
the concept of “deliberation.” To situate the need
for deliberation in schools, Parker asserts that educational
interactions that lead to democratic understandings can be
characterized in three ways. First, they increase the
interactions among diverse participants. Second, interaction is
fostered around common problems – whether focused on
academic subject matter or interpersonal relations. Third,
inclusive deliberation is expected, taught, and modeled. With
this background, Parker asserts that deliberation, which can be
employed at every level of education, is a creative and
problem-oriented experience, drawing on relationships among
participants and ultimately crafting a “particular kind of
democratic public culture among the deliberators” (p. 80).
Parker emphasizes that deliberation is not the only approach to
solving problems in democracies. Instead, he asserts, public
decision-making is more often characterized by voting, debate, or
negotiation. Yet, deliberation is particularly important for
strengthening relationships across difference, as more common
approaches to democratic interactions tend to set up adversarial
relationships that do not necessarily lead to a fuller
understanding of community, rather than individual, problems.
Referring to the underlying theme of the entire text, Parker
reminds us that dialogue across/within difference is essential to
the development of communities that are truly multicultural and
inclusive.
This work is informative on multiple levels.
Educators at all levels, as well as community activists and
others interested in democratic interactions, could benefit from
engaging in this text. A key strength of Parker’s work is
that it illustrates precisely what it advocates. Specifically, it
opens doors for conversation among the various strands of thought
that comprise citizenship education. It is exceptionally
well-referenced in ways that allow readers to seek further
sources and enter the debates that Parker frames. Through his
engaging text, Parker enters into deep and sustained dialogue
with important scholars, and introduces new ways of thinking
about their work. He further roots that dialogue in both
historical and contemporary problems and texts, thereby engaging
in democratic education at the same time as illustrating the
complexities of such engagement.
My reading of the text would have been enriched
had I been privy to several additional discussions. First, the
beginning of the book was substantially more engaging on a
theoretical level, whereas the second part was more directly
practical. For those persons wishing to translate the ideas posed
in this book into contexts other than those discussed here,
further discussion on how the prevailing ideas could be
translated into multiple contexts (particularly those at the
post-secondary level) would have been appreciated. Second,
stylistically, it was not always clear how the various chapters
were intertwined. As was indicated in the preface, many of the
chapters presented in this book were originally crafted for
different audiences. While clear attempts were made to build
bridges between the sections, at times the breaks between the
chapters created a loss of momentum that was so evident within
chapters. Third, while Parker provided examples from multiple
levels in K-12 education, I believe the discussion would have
benefited from an integration of knowledge about the education of
citizens in postsecondary education (e.g., Astin, 1993; Colby,
Ehrlich, Beaumont, & Stephens, 2003; Hamrick, 1998; Rhoads,
1998). Finally, while I appreciated the acknowledgement that the
discussions Parker presented in this book were difficult both to
understand and implement, I would nevertheless have appreciated a
fuller discussion on how democracy is imperfect and has been
misused. Does Parker believe that there is a need for students to
be critical of democracy itself? Does the deliberation that he
proposes about how to solve social problems go as far as a
critique of the deep underpinnings of a presumably beneficial
social arrangement? Especially because of his clear and thorough
knowledge of civil rights in particular and history more
generally, I would have welcomed his perspectives on this
important question.
As I finished reading this text, I was left with
the following questions: In what ways are schools and
universities currently functioning as places where students can
learn to be democratic citizens? In what ways are
educators’ efforts to promote deliberation in their
classrooms stymied or facilitated by administrative practices
that affect their ability to include students in real
problem-based learning? Conversely, in what ways are
administrators’ efforts to promote engagement hindered or
facilitated by faculty who do not see the benefits of such
approaches? How will the push for increased productivity and
accountability in our nation’s institutions affect
schools’ abilities to proceed in the manner Parker advises?
Further, in communities in which educational institutions remain
heavily segregated, and are often divided into the
“haves” and “have-nots,” how can the
diversity necessary for democratic deliberation be best fostered
and embraced? Parker’s text on Teaching democracy
speaks to all of these questions. Yet, it also emphasizes the
need for further dialogue and deliberation on the important
subject of educating diverse citizens for democratic
engagement.
References
Astin, A. W. (1993). Diversity and multiculturalism on the
campus: How are students affected? Change, 25(1), p.
44-49.
Cherryholmes, C. H. (1980). Social knowledge and citizenship
education: Two views of truth and criticism. Curriculum
Inquiry, 10. 115-151.
Colby, A., Ehrlich, T., Beaumont, E., & Stephens, J.
(2003). Educating citizens: Preparing America’s
undergraduates for lives of moral and civic responsibility.
San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
Hamrick, F. A. (1998). Democratic citizenship and student
activism. Journal of College Student Development, 39,
449-60.
Rhoads, R. A. (1998). Freedom’s web: Student activism
in an age of cultural diversity. Baltimore, MD: Johns
Hopkins.
Tocqueville, A. d. (1848/1969). Democracy in America.
Garden City, NY: Doubleday.
About the Reviewer
Becky Ropers-Huilman is an Associate Professor of
Higher Education and Women’s and Gender Studies at
Louisiana State University. Her scholarly interests focus on
social justice, college teaching, diversity, and activism in
higher education. Her work as appeared in The Review of Higher
Education, National Women’s Studies Association
Journal, and The International Journal of Qualitative
Studies in Education, as well as other professional outlets
and three books, including Feminist teaching in theory and
practice: Situating power and knowledge in poststructural
classrooms, Women in higher education: A feminist
perspective, and Gendered futures in higher education:
Critical perspectives for change.
~
ER home |
Reseņas Educativas |
Resenhas Educativas ~
~
overview | reviews | editors | submit | guidelines | announcements
~
| |