|
This review has been accessed times since November 29, 2004
Robins, Kevin and Webster, Frank. (2002). The Virtual
University? Knowledge, Markets and Management. New York:
Oxford University Press.
Pp. x + 332
$24.50 ISBN 0-19-925793-0
Reviewed by John Rothfork
Northern Arizona University
November 29, 2004
I was initially excited to discover this book from Oxford
University Press knowing that Oxford publishes many outstanding
works. Unfortunately, this collection isn’t one of them.
The anthology comprises 14 mostly journeyman essays that give the
authors a chance to drone on about their personal interests
rather than respond to a charge given by able editors to inform
us about the emerging polices of distance education and how these
contribute to restructuring higher education. The focus seems
more British than American, although about 40% of the authors are
American. Most of the essays are ho-hum; some are offered as the
author’s stock or repeated message, others are taken from
larger works. For example, a chapter from David Noble’s
Digital Diploma Mills tells the story of how in the 1920s
Columbia and the University of Chicago, among other universities,
promoted correspondence education as a purely money making
venture. Enrollment fees were nonrefundable and “together
with fraudulent advertising and an indiscriminate enrolment
policy, inescapably perfunctory instruction [by adjuncts]
produced a dropout rate of 80 per cent” (p. 292). When a
rare student completed the courses she would find them of little
value because the credits could not be applied towards earning a
degree, even from the school that offered them (p. 294). Noble
suggests that distance education via the Internet may, in many
cases, repeat this shoddy history. He asks, “If online
education were truly the equivalent of classroom education, as
its proponents suggest, why won’t the elite colleges and
universities that have so avidly embraced it give full credit for
this form of instruction?” (Noble, p. 23).
Almost no one will give a direct answer to this question
because it reveals too much. I think an important part of the
answer is that senior faculty will not learn computer skills
required to put their classes online, nor do the time-consuming
work that online teaching requires. For different reasons, senior
faculty and administrators agree that online course development
and delivery is not comparable to publishing and is not evidence
of professional growth. I assume many administrators are happy
with the situation in which regular faculty give away their
academic territory to more compliant IT (instructional
technology) technicians and adjunct facilitators to offer a
semblance of rigorous academic programs. The courses and programs
are offered but they are ersatz. The reason they are not the real
thing is that the “real” professor, who is a
published authority in the area, may be involved in designing the
course but not in teaching or delivering it. Some courses at some
schools are accepted as “regular” credits. The online
courses I teach at Northern Arizona University offer English
department graduate credit that is undifferentiated from
traditional classroom courses. In contrast, several California
state universities offer what appear to be very similar courses.
But they are offered by extension divisions, taught by adjuncts,
and cannot be used to fulfill requirements in a degree program.
(See, for example
<http://www.unex.ucr.edu/certificates/technical.html>).
Texas Tech has embarked on an interesting experiment in distance
education. They are the national leader in the area of technical
writing and they have just begun (fall 2004) to offer an online
Ph.D. program
<http://www.english.ttu.edu/tc/PhDOnline.htm>. This venture
will likely succeed because it is not driven by the hope to
attract thousands of students to produce windfall profits. The
program is controlled by the English department and involves the
regular faculty in developing and teaching the classes. Concord
Law School offers another model of distance education that
involves “real” faculty
<http://www.concord.kaplan.edu/info/custom/concord/faculty/
faculty.asp?GUID=9DC3002583BE4B6A898C6C0691125B29238830058932521263>.
These three schools offer examples of programs where the major
difference from traditional education is in the medium of
instruction. Tenured faculty continue to develop and teach
courses. In contrast, a great deal of distance education is
predicated on the bait and switch technique using branding to
suggest that “customers” can buy a prestigious degree
from a “real” university through online education.
Students then find that rudimentary entertainment courses or
minimally developed courses that hardly do more than offer a
reading list are “facilitated” by ill paid M.A. level
adjuncts trained to provide customer service satisfaction. They
are not experts in some discipline who might offer rigorous
professional judgments that continue to control
“real” professions and disciplines.
Western Governors’ University (WGU)
Noble’s chapter is preceded by Timothy Luke’s
essay describing the development of Virginia Tech’s
Cyberschool <http://www.cddc.vt.edu/cyber/index.html/>,
which the political science professor nominates as only
“one among the nearly one thousand online universities that
Forbes has counted out on the WWW” (p. 259).
Unfortunately, he provides no citation to allow us to examine the
list, which I could not find at Forbes
<http://www.forbes.com/lists/>. Luke castigates what he
calls “Noble’s paranoid anticommercialism” (p.
271) even though his bibliography suggests that he has only read
a short online description of Digital Diploma Mills (2001)
<http://www.firstmonday.dk/issues/issue3_1/noble/>. Luke
believes that “Critiques like Noble’s run afoul of an
assumption of ‘Disneyification’” (p. 272). By
this he means that critics like Noble imagine big business to be
a monolithic and fascist force possessing the power to
arbitrarily mold society in any way it wishes. In contrast, Luke
reminds us that “online learning already has been
developing at universities for five years using much more basic
and inexpensive techniques to generate a new mix” of
interactive forms (p. 272). I doubt that anyone involved would
agree that distance education is inexpensive, including Luke
himself, who admits, “Digitalization costs more, not
less” (p. 270).
Prof. Luke’s other irritant is the Western
Governor’s University (WGU:
<http://www.wgu.edu/about_WGU/who_we_are.asp>), which he
uses in a straw man argument. It is hard for me to imagine what
institution WGU might threaten. The “WGU Mentors”
page makes it clear that it also subscribes to the model of
course facilitators and adjuncts, but it is hardly a match for
the University of Phoenix. In November 2003, The University of
Phoenix enrolled 91,000 online students. Luke is worried that
“by 2006, or ten years after its inception, the WGU hopes
to enroll 8,000 students in its competency-based degree
programmes” (p. 262). He thinks “the real innovation
of the WGU is this effort to create a new symbolic economy of
academic achievement, moral economy of personal choice, and
public economy of lower costs” (p. 263). What does this
mean? Apparently Prof. Luke is concerned that WGU will be
mistaken for a state university, will give degrees away by
crediting “life experience” in place of real academic
courses, and will charge less than Phoenix or DeVry. Although
Luke has two degrees from the University of Arizona, he sounds
strangely foreign and misinformed in writing, “Fortunately
for now, the WGU lacks a great deal of credibility: it comes from
the weakest, newest, and most powerless part of the US, or the
Mountain West. Not one of its member institutions is considered a
top-tier school” (p. 263). This is bad writing and sloppy
research. WGU includes the states of Texas, Washington, Colorado,
and Arizona. Is Luke is unaware that the University of Washington
ranks second, after Johns Hopkins, on the list of universities
receiving federal research money or that the flagship
universities of these four Western states are listed among
“The Top American Research Universities”
<http://thecenter.ufl.edu/research2002.pdf>?
Perhaps Prof. Luke would think I am wrong to associate
“top-tier” schools with research universities. If
Luke has some other basis for his judgment, it is perhaps implied
in his conventional understanding of education:
The WGU model of building a virtual university is
unfortunate, because it purposely seems devoted to developing
substitutes for traditional public and private universities by
undercutting their missions of liberal education, civic
socialization, and universal enlightenment with narrowly-focused
labour force training agendas (p. 263).
Calling distance education unfortunate, upstart, and plebian
is not going to make it go away. Prof. Luke does offer the right
suggestion when he writes, “The virtual university is a
perfect place for academics to enter these discussions. Who
builds it, how it is built, why it will be built, and where it is
built are all questions whose answers will reshape academic
life” (p. 278). But he is himself too much the traditional
professor to accept that many of those involved in restructuring
the university are likely to come from off-campus. Luke’s
outlook and methods are illustrated in this rambling point about
the “cyber space” nature of Internet communication
and how this may influence one’s sense of identity:
Moving from the spatio-temporal perspectives of
territoriality to the acceleration effects of instant
communication, all of Earth’s inhabitants may well wind up
thinking of themselves more as contemporaries than as
citizens; they may in the process slip out of the
contiguous space, distributed by quota, of the old Nation-State
(or City-State), which harboured the demos, and into the
atopic community of a “Planet-State” that unfolds as
“a sort of omnipolitan periphery whose centre
will be nowhere and circumference everywhere” (p.
274).
Too many of the essays indulge in this kind of ivory tower
gobbledygook.
Martin Trow: Consequences for Higher Education
The clearest and more daring essay was written by Martin Trow
<http://ishi.lib.berkeley.edu/cshe/mtrow/> who is a
colleague of David L. Kirp. They are both faculty at
UC–Berkeley’s School of Public Policy (see my review
of Kirp’s Shakespeare, Einstein, and the Bottom Line:
The Marketing of Higher Education (2003):
<http://edrev.asu.edu/reviews/rev302.htm>). Prof. Trow
identifies five important points.
- The speed of change in hardware, software, and even the
pedagogy of online instruction is so swift “that many big
American universities are not doing much, if any,
institution-wide planning for the adoption of the ICTs
[information and communication technologies], but are giving
these decisions over to departments and research units” (p.
303). An associated series of events—the spectacular and
costly failures of Columbia, Cornell, NYU, and Britain’s
Open University to create national or international distance
programs—also cause university presidents to pause. Trow
mentions more failures: “Everywhere we turn, we see major
commitments by big institutions coming to naught […].
California created a Virtual University a few years ago, and gave
it up a few months later. The Western Governors University, begun
with much high level support, has scaled down its ambitions
sharply” (p. 303). Trow also mentions the “total
confusion in our courts and legislatures about what to do about
Napster” and intellectual property rights that either seem
meaningless anachronisms or impediments to the free flow of
information on the Internet (p. 304).
- Internet based research and education blurs and weakens
institutional and discipline boundaries making “all study
inherently interdisciplinary.” The research library
conceived as a vaguely monastic and elite institution to control
access to rare information is a thing of the past.
“Information comes online from everywhere, and liberates
scholars from dependence on their own libraries” (pp.
305-6). This is heady for the mid-career scholar who knows how to
do research. It is typically confusing for the undergraduate and
novice because “the computer and web have an inherent bias
towards research rather than scholarship” (p. 305). What
Trow means is that the Internet provides raw data rather than
scholarly explanation and guidance. It is not a classroom; it is
not an edited anthology. When it seems to provide explanation,
the novice finds it difficult to distinguish proselytism,
propaganda, pseudo-science, and sales pitches from true
scholarship. If one is not trained to understand rhetorical
context and to interpret data in some academic or professional
context, the “facts” either remain puzzling or are
arbitrarily associated. In contrast to the Internet, research
libraries are built by a long process of careful and learned
judgments in selecting acquisitions. The Internet offers no
reliable clues about the meaning of what we find there. Consider
the first male pregnancy site:
<http://www.malepregnancy.com/>. I have followed Mr.
Lee’s alleged pregnancy for four years. When my colleagues
ask their composition students if this site offers legitimate
information they might use in a research paper, nearly half are
likely to think it is legitimate.
Prof. Trow identifies an essential point about the pragmatic
nature of education:
While research is increasingly independent of its traditional
venues, research training is not. As far ahead as we can see, the
physically close and extended relationship of student and mentor
will be necessary for a student to become a scientist or
scholar” (p. 316).
This pragmatic understanding of knowledge and education,
offered years ago by Bucky Fuller among others, is perennially
discovered by those who persist long enough in trying to find out
why Star Trek notions of what computers can do fail (see
Dreyfus). The problem is that the Internet makes ever more
information easily available to the consumer or entrepreneur who,
as “customer,” is unguided by the context and
technique supplied by years of education or professional
practice. Trow says, “Commercial firms are indifferent to
the status of the university or college where research of
interest to them can be done. And with broader access to all
institutions, the students in different kinds of institutions
begin to look more alike” (p. 306). Initially this is
liberating, allowing talented and insightful students to
communicate with elite scholars, but the disrespect of academic
boundaries cannot be sustained when, for example, half of the
students (apparently informed by John Dewey’s pervasive
political paradigm that requires everything to be discussed and
voted on) feel entitled to express their opinion about Mr.
Lee’s pregnancy without feeling obligated to learn enough
about the biology of human reproduction to know that the
proposition is absurd.
- Prof. Trow’s clinical and descriptive tone is
frightening when he coolly predicts the erosion and loss of the
familiar routine and context for much of higher education below
the elite level where coaching and mentorship are indispensable
for educating the truly gifted and talented. First he makes the
usual point about commodification, writing that distance
education transforms “knowledge into a commodity to be
bought from scientists and scholars and sold over the internet
worldwide.” Prof. Trow makes sure we get the point that it
is not simply the objects of knowledge that become commodities,
but “the teaching itself, and not just the books that are
instruments of teaching.” Teaching is either tacitly
invested in the commodity so that someone from the same culture
understands the context and application or it is considered
inessential until end users begin to complain or ignore the
product (p. 307). “Here we see the blurring of the
traditional distinction between secondary and higher
education” in which secondary level students may have a
general notion about a subject but lack a detailed and
performance based knowledge of the techniques needed to produce
or use professional knowledge. Prof. Trow predicts that
“the rationalization of teaching through the new
technologies must tend to reduce even further the professional
status of the academic.” He says “we have seen it
happen in secondary school systems around the world” (p.
311) and I would add that we see it rapidly changing the
community college, which currently relies on adjuncts to teach
65% of the classes. It is not difficult to predict that the same
trend will erode teaching at undistinguished, non-research
universities where the difference between minimal competence and
excellence is either unrecognized or a matter of bluster.
- Prof. Trow states the obvious, that until now distance
education has been:
less immediately useful for courses which involve the search
for insight and understanding in art and ideas, where a teacher
wants to be in the company of one or a few students, each with a
copy of a book in his or her hand, exploring the significance and
meaning of a passage or character or event or poem or
philosophical idea (p. 308).
This description of an honors class is not likely to change,
but to be supplemented in various ways. Trow mentions medieval
scholars from around the country “studying an illuminated
manuscript more closely and effectively through an interactive
video connection” than they could have had they all been in
the same room (p. 308). The PBS science program Nova offered an
even more convincing example in a recent program concerning the
use of computer technology to recover some of Archimedes’
incredible and nearly lost work
<http://www.pbs.org/wgbh/nova/archimedes/>.
- Prof. Trow again states the obvious that most of us overlook
or deny, namely that many undergraduates are primarily or
initially interested in the university for the sports, parties,
nightlife, and opportunities to meet girls or guys; and because
the alternative is to get a dull job. Some parents are interested
in “offloading late adolescents” (p. 315) into a kind
of half-way house institution where they are less likely to get
into criminal mischief and may pick up job skills. I like to
imagine Prof. Trow addressing Prof. Luke when he says:
The point here is that the survival of the traditional
university does not depend on its maintaining a near monopoly of
advanced teaching and research—a monopoly which it has
already lost. The traditional university performs a variety of
other functions, some having little to do with education per
se (p. 316).
Nostalgia, Haughtiness, and Sermons
John Urry expresses nostalgia for a “relatively
slow-moving curricula and traditions of scholarly work”
that used to be “organized in terms of a daily cycle of
unchangeable time-tabled classes, a seasonal cycle of weeks,
terms and years, a lengthy cycle of degrees, and traditions and
ritual that hark back to Medieval Europe.” He implies that
the earlier academic pace and aesthetics have been scraped for
what sounds like an American Main Street notion of college;
“‘just-for-you’ (and ‘right now’)
modes of higher education” (p. 24). Urry’s metaphor
is one of cultural loss that fails to hide his upper class bias.
Urry expresses a wish for university life to slow down or escape
from “this chaotic, mobile, global landscape as analogous
to the internet, as unstable, contingent, and fluid-like”
as possible (p. 29). Naturally, he doesn’t tell us who is
to pay for this refuge and leisurely pace. He notes the concern
for university branding in which “McDonalds is the paradigm
case.” He develops a bitter analogy to suggest that the
emerging university will operate like a McDonalds franchise to
offer “low skilled standardized jobs” to adjuncts;
“new products” or programs resembling “Chicken
McNuggets” that owe as much for their form to advertising
and media technology as to their organic origin; and debased
pseudo-rituals suggested by the student slang of
“grazing,” which means “the eating of
standardized fast food bought from take-out restaurants” as
one rushes down the street towards some frantic and meaningless
engagement. Urry asks, “There are apparently 140,000
students now doing UK degrees without actually being at a UK
institution; what we can ask is the product that they are
consuming?” (p. 24). The implication is that they are not
learning to be gentlemen.
Gerald Delanty offers an impressionist history of higher
education that illustrates the trope of loss and decay,
specifically a decline from British standards of class sliding
towards American chaos and déclassé gluttony. Delanty
finds the model for the university in the imperial German
Enlightenment project that hoped to bring “about the
rationalization of culture in the name of universalistic
science.” In the twentieth century America developed
“the ‘civic university’—based on
disciplinary organized knowledge and the accreditation of
professionals.” Delanty predicts that in “the coming
global revolution of the twenty-first century […] the
university dissolves disciplinarity, institutionalizes market
values and enters the post-industrial information age” (p.
32). These three stages can be associated with the vocabulary of
social class. The first model “was designed to produce
gentlemen and clerics” (p. 35). “The American
university sought to make the university serve the civic
community” as it understood itself, which is to say that
African Americans, Native Americans, Hispanics, Asians, and women
were either invisible or consigned to silent and servile roles
(p. 37). The postmodern university resembles the Internet in
offering information for personal and idiosyncratic use because,
says Delanty, “universalistic values have withdrawn from
most areas of life, leaving only procedural forms of rationality
in the place of substantive values” (45).
“Withdrawn” is it? This slick passive voice
construction advocates the conservative pole in the culture wars.
When were universalistic values anything more than colonial and
class oppression? Delanty’s ending is theatrical. His
suggestions of cultural confusion, indirection, and totally free
individuals needing professors, if not aristocrats, to guide
their life choices is, to say the least, exaggerated. The
supposedly decultured individuals that Delanty images continue to
speak English, apparently use the Internet, inhabit some
political realm, and continue to follow bourgeois cultural
scripts. This gives Delanty the hope that the university
“can provide the structures for public debate between
expert and lay cultures” and if we fail to generate some
easy consensus, then “Perhaps it is the role of the
university to enable society to live with choice and
uncertainty” (p. 46).
Prof. Maso Miyoshi teaches literature. His essay is a rambling
complaint about how the current discussion of the emerging
virtual university is “solely concerned with the
institutional economy” and has “nothing whatever to
say on the humanities, as if this branch of learning had already
vanished” (p. 69). Miyoshi advises that “we should
perhaps never talk about the modern university without recalling
Joseph Conrad’s Heart of Darkness.” The
relevance becomes apparent only when we recognize the implied
claim that the forces involved in restructuring American higher
education are no different than the European nineteenth century
colonial oppression of Africa. Although he reports giving his
paper on no fewer than eight previous occasions, Prof.
Miyoshi’s moral indignation about the status of the
humanities in the virtual university is both too general and too
personal. Miyoshi offers the general litany involved in tracing
the decline of the traditional university: “instead of
regular faculty, contingency instructors”; “the
for-profit behemoth, the University of Phoenix” (p. 58);
the CEO as “the only model for presidents and chancellors
of universities” (p. 59); and “the emergence of a
global academic industry” (p. 68). So, what is to be done?
He says the university is “no longer selling out; it has
already been sold and bought. The deed has been written and
signed, and the check already signed, too.” Nonetheless,
the literature professor wants to continue some kind of good
fight “to right the situation, to null the transaction and
be just to all on earth.” To do this “we may have to
relearn the sense of the world, the totality, that includes all
peoples in every race, class, and gender” (p. 78), but this
will apparently not be a lesson learned in literature classes at
the new university where Miyoshi says the humanities will be
offered “as a managerial training programme in metropolitan
manners, style, and fashion, set aside for the socially
‘elite’ institutions” (p. 77). Urry and Delanty
complain that distance education exposes and erodes the subsidy
necessary to support elite education while Miyoshi complains that
it serves only the likes of Babbitt.
Benson and Harkavy also offer a rehash of papers “we
have published elsewhere, beginning in 1991” (p. 169). In
“Saving the Soul of the University” they express
nearly religious ardor for their “proposed American system
of higher education,” based, they think, on John
Dewey’s work, which they “have to confess” they
“knew almost nothing about” until 1985 when they
began “to improve university-community relationships”
(p. 195) for the University of Pennsylvania. They offer a
socialist vision in which research competition for pure knowledge
is the most egregious sin. They preach that the “egoistic,
self-centered and self-aggrandizing competition among
professors” as well as “the competitive ranking and
rating game” (p. 205) produces “both university
commodification and university-community conflict” (p.
199). They are absurdly parochial in making the suggestion that
all higher education “should explicitly make solving the
problem of the American [K-12] schooling system their
highest institutional priority; their contributions to its
solution should count heavily both in assessing their
institutional performance and in responding to their requests for
renewed or increased financial support” (p. 209).
Putting the University Online
In addition to the chapter from David Noble’s book, the
editors include a chapter from James Cornford and Neil
Pollock’s important book, Putting the University Online:
Information, Technology and Organizational Change (2003).
See the Education Review at
<http://edrev.asu.edu/reviews/rev274.htm> as well as my
review in Kairos
<http://english.ttu.edu/kairos/9.1/binder.html?reviews/rothfork/index.htm>.
Conford and Pollock’s argument follows Foucault’s
theory, which they awkwardly derive from Actor Network Theory.
Foucault’s point is that how something is done largely
defines what it is or what it means. We do not find ready-made
ideas and theories; these are socially constructed, including the
idea of the university. Cornford and Pollock are interested in
the effects of academic management software as well as the
effects of distance education software and methods. If professors
forgo traditional modes of teaching and scholarship to facilitate
online course delivery and increasingly do assessment clerking
with academic management software, then the question is, what
does it mean to be a professor? “The nature of academic
work is changing as scholars find themselves using more
technology” (p. 101). These choices seem to be either
innocuous methodological preferences or to be technical and
administrative decisions. In either case, senior faculty are
mostly relieved not to be pressed into developing and delivering
online courses. The result is that they give away their
profession to IT staff and to adjuncts. Professors complain that
when one of their colleagues retires or moves, the tenure track
position evaporates because the money has moved to support a half
dozen compliant adjuncts and IT technicians. Cornford and
Pollock’s book is clumsily written but important in
explaining how the restructuring of higher education is taking
place without much notice or clamor because the changes are in
how the university operates rather than in what
professors teach in class. The adjuncts who replace professors
will be in no position to complain about academic freedom since
the model for what they do is largely offered by telemarketing:
they follow a script developed by an increasingly centrally
controlled institution committed to what the dean at the Fremont
(San Francisco), California DeVry campus told David Kirp was
“a ‘total quality management’
environment” (p. 243).
Charles Crook means to offer a piece on the psychology of
learning involved with distance education or as he puts it,
“how our thinking about virtualization might be informed by
psychological perspectives” and how this “has
influenced the design of educational technology.” Like many
of the other contributors, he gets lost on the way to spend his
time telling us about behaviourism, cognitivism, and
constructivism without making clear applications to distance
learning. He does make one interesting observation concerning
master teachers in traditional classrooms who “seemed
actively to avoid the precision and explicitness of the
software.” Instead of offering a cookbook recipe to follow,
such teachers elaborated “an invitation for the learner
(listener/reader) to engage actively with the presentation”
(p. 121).
Philip Agre contrasts what he calls the traditional
“community model” of the university with that of
“the commodity model—the university as a competitor
in a marketplace” (p. 210). He cites other scholars to make
the usual points. For example, he suggests that “Faculty
might be deskilled in” the context of “a radicalized
commodity model” to be “reduced effectively to the
status of teaching assistants who tutor students on the material
in the video.” He knows that actually teaching the material
offers what he calls “value added,” but wonders if
students will “pay the extra cost to get the virtues of the
more labour-intensive programme?” (p. 211). He recognizes
Cornford and Pollock’s concern for academic management
software; “that the profession’s very institutions
(conferences, journals, social networks, everyday
information-seeking, and collaboration) may grow together with
the disciplinary community of practice of the university.”
Agre does not perceive a threat to academic labour in this and
apparently is unconcerned about the proliferation of academic
bureaucracy. He sees an opportunity for “publication and
peer review […] extended to occupations that have not
historically organized their own conferences and journals”
(213). We now have university “professionals”
dedicated, for example, to staging conventions and
conferences.
Professor Trow’s essay provides almost the only reason
to obtain this book. This essay, along with others, is available
from Prof. Trow’s Website (see Works Cited). The excerpts
from Noble’s book and from Cornford and Pollock’s
book provide lesser reasons to buy the book, only because
obtaining their short books is preferable.
References
Cornford, James and Neil Pollock. (2003). Putting the
University Online: Information, Technology and Organizational
Change. London: Open University Press.
Dreyfus, Hubert L. (1992, revised from 1979). What
Computers Still Can’t Do: A Critique of Artificial
Reason. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Kirp, David L. (2003). Shakespeare, Einstein, and the
Bottom Line: The Marketing of Higher Education. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Noble, David F. (2001). Digital Diploma Mills: The
Automation of Higher Education.
New York: Monthly Review Press.
Trow, Martin. “Some Consequences of the New Information
and Communication Technology for Higher Education”
<http://ishi.lib.berkeley.edu/cshe/mtrow/>.
About the Reviewer
John Rothfork
English Department
Northern Arizona University
Flagstaff, AZ 86011
John.Rothfork@nau.edu
John Rothfork teaches online courses in a graduate certificate
program in professional and technical writing at Northern Arizona
University. His Website is at http://oak.ucc.nau.edu/jgr6/.
~
ER home |
Reseņas Educativas |
Resenhas Educativas ~
~
overview | reviews | editors | submit | guidelines | announcements
~
| |