This review has been accessed times since January 1, 2005
Fine, Michelle; Weis, Lois; Powell, Linda C. and Wong, L. Mun
(Eds.). (1997). Off White: Readings on Race, Power, and
Society. New York: Routledge.
Pp. xii+366.
$80 (Cloth) ISBN: 0415913012
$25.99 (Paper) ISBN: 0415913020
Reviewed by Audrey Thompson University of Utah
November 12, 1999
Under the terms of mainstream U.S. ideology, racism is
usually understood in one of two ways. Either it is viewed as
an expression of personal prejudice, dislike, or hatred, or it
is regarded as matter of racially biased rules. Insofar as
racism is associated with overt dislike for members of other
races, it is likely to be seen as a fringe ideology that, while
common earlier in the century and lingering in the attitudes of
some members of the older generation, is now so unacceptable
that it is endorsed only by white supremacist hate groups.
(Note 1) Well-meaning whites often note, for example, that it is
no longer permissible in polite circles to make derogatory
comments about blacks; their grandparents and even their parents
may still talk that way, but they themselves are horrified by
such talk. Seen from this perspective, racism is a kind of
character flaw that infected many white people in the past but
will have disappeared altogether by the time that white children
of the present generation become adults. Indeed, some whites
complain that racism-as-bigotry is now pretty much confined to
people of color: "Look at all those angry blacks and Mexicans
who hate whites. They're the ones stirring up resentment
between the races." (Note 2)
Alternatively, racism may be viewed as a system of rules
based on irrelevant racial criteria. Typically treated as more
or less interchangeable with "bias" or "unfairness," this second
analysis of racism is often invoked in discussions of
segregation. In visits to elementary schools, Herbert Kohl
(1995) found that discussions of landmark events like the
Montgomery bus boycott, for example, focused on the unfairness
of racial segregation. By representing whites and blacks as
responding with equal outrage to such unfairness, white teachers
managed to suggest that race was almost an incidental issue. In
any case, these teachers implied, discrimination against blacks
was a thing of the past. Ironically, whites often see racism in
the form of discrimination against whites as very much
alive. The real issue with racism-as-unfairness, many whites
believe, is "reverse discrimination." Not only in casual
conversation but in scholarly and media discussions, complaints
about how unfairly affirmative action treats white men are
regularly offered up as sober, balanced commentary on a
pervasive problem (Giroux, 1997).
Both the personal-bias and the unfair-rules views offer
colorblind accounts of racism; even though they are about race,
they have been deracialized. A definition of racism is
colorblind if it assumes that noticing race is itself racist.
Colorblind definitions of racism usually assume that racism does
not have a material or institutional form; instead, racism is
considered to be a matter of personal attitudes or perceptions.
Thus, under the terms of colorblind racism, Chicana/os or
African Americans who call a policy racist may themselves be
identified as racist because they have used race as a perceptual
filter. Using colorblind frameworks, it is as easy to call
people of color racist as it is to call whites racist. If
anything, it may be easier to call people of color
racist, since people of color are more likely than whites to
challenge the terms of colorblindness.
Whiteness theories not only refuse colorblindness as a
generic framework but draw attention to the variety of ways in
which supposedly universal, colorblind values are articulated to
whiteness. The project of whiteness theorists is to
problematize the normalization of whiteness as racelessness, to
make "visible . . . what was previously unseen" (Foucault, 1980,
p. 50). In psychologically oriented whiteness theories, the
primary focus is on the development of a healthy white identity
that is aware of but does not participate in racism. Racism,
here, is usually understood as an attitude or belief system
perpetuated by systematic cultural ignorance, on the one hand,
and personal insensitivity, on the other. The solution to
racism, as seen from this perspective, is for individual whites
to confront and overcome their suppressed commitments to white
supremacy and learn to embrace diversity as a shared good. For
psychological theorists of whiteness, a healthy white racial
identity will not become possible until whites confront and
accept their whiteness (abandoning colorblindness), acknowledge
the privileges of whiteness, and take a consistently anti-racist
stance. The keys to developing a healthy white identity, then,
are 1) developing an awareness of whiteness, including
white privilege; and 2) acting in ways that make use of that
knowledge to challenge personal and institutional racism.
Most socially oriented whiteness theorists, on the other
hand, are concerned less with the question of what counts as a
healthy personal orientation to race and racism than with the
question of how race and racism have come to take the form they
do in the first place. Both discourse and material approaches
to whiteness understand racism in terms of the social
mechanisms that falsely legitimate whiteness as normative or
superior. Inspired in part by Toni Morrison's (1992) brilliant
Playing in the Dark, this literature characterizes
whiteness as a purportedly neutral or normal condition that
depends on materially and ideologically enforced contrasts to
blackness or brownness for its normative status. In other
words, it addresses whiteness and racism as social constructions
(whether ideological or institutional). According to discursive
and materialist perspectives, racism is not a personal deviation
from egalitarian ideals but a specifically "normal"because
normalizedstance legitimated by the dominant society. If
racism is structured into our very environment, as these
theorists argue, then it cannot be dismantled through a change
of heart. Either racism must be challenged by non-"normal"
behaviors that disrupt whiteness (as self-proclaimed "race
traitors" urge) or we must change the material and ideological
constructions that privilege whiteness (as revolutionaries and
reconstructionists argue).
Despite the important differences between these three
paradigms, psychological, discourse, and material approaches to
whiteness theory agree in rejecting colorblindness as the
solution to racism. Whereas colorblindness "leave[s] the
assumptions of whiteness in place" (Billig, 1997, p. 155),
whiteness theory challenges those assumptions. To alter the
racial status quo, whiteness theorists argue, we must begin by
unravelling and exposing the network of white lies about
whiteness, blackness, and brownness. Because it refuses any
acknowledgment of racism in the name of racial
inequality, colorblindness is one of the most seductive of white
lies. Whiteness theories demystify white lies, allowing us to
see the costs of maintaining whiteness as an ideal.
Whiteness Theories and Off White
For the most part, whiteness theorists' emphasis is not on
whiteness as an announced value but whiteness as a suppressed,
invisible privilege. (Note 3) In a racist society, whites are
privileged by their color in ways they never notice. A white
person may not feel privileged, but if she can walk into
a department store and never think about whether the store
detectives regard her as a probable shoplifter, she is
privileged by her whiteness. African Americans, along with many
other people of color, must be prepared to be stopped and asked
to open their bags for inspection.
Whiteness thus understood matters less because of its
connections to the overt pro-white racism of white supremacists
than because of its normalized statusits apparently generic
and unbiased quality. It is powerful because so many of us do
not know how to think about it. Kept unnamed and invisible,
whiteness remains "just out of argumentative reach" (Billig,
1997, p. 152). Not surprisingly, what whiteness is and how it
is related to racism are far from settled questions among
theorists of whiteness. Despite considerable overlap, the
different strains in the whiteness literature have taken quite
distinct positions on what whiteness is and how it is to be
problematized.
Discourse Theories of Whiteness
Discourse approaches to whiteness theory focus on the
privileging of whiteness in ideology, symbol systems, and
popular culture. In a racialized and racist society, not only
cultural but political, intellectual, and moral values are
organized around whiteness as the center. Moral values such as
generosity, cultural values such as femininity, political values
such as equal opportunity, and intellectual values such as
objectivityalthough nominally colorblindare articulated
to how whites perceive themselves. Generosity, for example, is
a virtue articulated to privilege (including class, gender,
race, and other social privileges). In the U.S., we do not
count the sacrifices and losses incurred by black slaves in
service to whites as "generous," yet white slave owners who
taught their slaves to read or who freed them as a reward for
their loyalty may well be seen as generous ("given the
context"). (Note 4) To say that such values are articulated to
whiteness is not necessarily to say that they are values
reserved for whites. On the contrary, they are likely to be
treated as generic norms. But while individual members of
non-white groups may be able to display these values, they cannot
set new terms for what is to count as femininity,
generosity, objectivity, or equal opportunity. Whiteness sets
the terms for value.
According to discursive theories of whiteness, the tools by
which we construct meaning in a racist societyour language,
symbol systems, fine art, science, and the popular media
teach us to think of value in relation to whiteness, with the
result that competing values are automatically constructed as
"other" and therefore as deviant or threatening. The Bell
Curve, for example, used the purportedly neutral language of
science to characterize white, suburban, middle-class values "as
the epitome of wholesomeness and completeness" (McCarthy,
Buendía, Mills, Meacham, Godina, Wilson-Brown, Seferian, &
Souchet, 1996, p. 258), linking outsiders to "disease and
degeneracy" (p. 259). Such constructions of value depend on
dichotomies that definitively separate "us" from "them." Only
insofar as we deconstruct and disrupt the prevailing, racialized
organization of value, discursive theorists suggest, will
whiteness lose its authoritative and normalized character, and
thus its power to demonize blackness and brownness.
The power whiteness has to shape our perception of value
depends on its never being acknowledged as an organizing
principle. Insofar as whiteness is normalized, its privileges
are erased and whites can assume that "merit," "success," and
other measures of value represent colorblind standards; if
whites outperform non-whites according to these standards, then
whites are demonstrably more deserving than non-whites. Indeed,
the privileges of whiteness may be erased to such a degree that
whiteness is characterized as an embattled position. Taking
their entitlements for granted, whites shift attention from
their own advantages to the threat that others pose to their way
of life. An excellent example of such discursive theorizing in
the Off White collection is Louise Kidder's (1997)
description of the white, expatriate community in a South Indian
city. The Europeans and North Americans whom Kidder interviewed
were quite wealthy in comparison to the majority of Indians, yet
they did not see themselves as privileged, for they focused on
differences in privileges within the group of expatriates
rather than comparisons to "the average person on the street"
(p. 159). Since the comparisons in which the relatively
privileged expatriates were interested concerned other whites,
"their refrigerators, phones, and cars served not as the figure
but the ground: what stood out for them was how vulnerable they
were" (p. 161). Taking their whiteness and its privileges for
granted, they worried about possible threats to those
privileges.
The mechanisms by which the expatriates legitimated their
own privilege included gossip of the
you-just-can't-get-good-help-nowadays variety. Foregrounding
their own perceived
vulnerability, the expatriate community continually circulated
stories about being taken advantage of by Indians. "'They
really know how to cheat you. . . . [T]hey'll try to cheat you
as far as they can, but if you get smart and threaten 'em,
they'll stop'" (Kidder, 1997, p. 161). We/them lines were so
clearly drawn that new members of the expatriate community
coming in without any desire for servantssoon "slipped into
positions that had been prepared by colonial rulers" (p. 158).
From those positions, any question of deservingness looked
clear-cut. When things went wrong in the household, the Indian
servants were blamed, but when things went well, their white
employers were most likely to "accept most of the credit because
they were in charge" (p. 164).
Another discursively oriented chapter in Off White
demonstrates how movies, television news, weekly news magazines,
and other popular culture media in the U. S. circulate
"resentment" narratives that position the inner city as
undermining everything that the white, suburban middle class has
worked so hard to achieve. Resentment narratives characterize
suburban needs as congruent with "national interests" while
dismissing "the needs of the inner city . . . as a wasteful
'social agenda'" (McCarthy, Rodriguez, Meecham, David,
Wilson-Brown, Godina, Supryia, & Buendía, p. 234). Movie versions of
the resentment narrative often enact white fantasies of revenge.
In some movies, white male vigilantes may take on the corrupt
inner city single-handedly to restore moral order. In other
movies, revenge is exacted indirectly, as black gangsters suffer
the inevitable costs of their violence and lawlessness. Such
narratives help to position whiteness as righteous, under siege,
but in the end triumphant over the immoral forces associated
with poverty and darkness.
The discursive theorists represented in Off White
emphasize the ideological mechanisms by which whiteness is
maintained and affirmed as normal or superior. Deconstructing
racial discourses, they suggest, allows us to identify the
hidden workings of power. Some of the other whiteness theorists
working in the discourse tradition, however, are interested less
in deconstructing than in disrupting white privilege.
For self-described "race traitors" such as Noel Ignatiev and
John Garvey (1996), whiteness itself can be abolished if we
disrupt the "normal operation" of "the institutions that
reproduce race as a social category" (p. 3). If enough whites
commit racial treason, Ignatiev and Garvey argue, the resulting
anarchy will make it impossible for the mechanisms of white
privilege to work.
This latter position has come in for a good deal of
criticism from structurally oriented whiteness theorists.
Although structural analyses are usually compatible with the
kind of discursive analyses found in Kidder (1997) and McCarthy
et al. (1997), they are specifically opposed to "race traitor"
approaches because of the tendency of race traitors to reject
whiteness altogether. As Linda Martín Alcoff (1998) puts it,
"whites cannot disavow whiteness." A white person may choose
not to avail herself of her privileges, but she remains eligible
for those privileges even if she "work[s] hard to avoid them"
(p. 17). For structural or material theorists, what matters is
how the system operates to serve whites even without
their knowledge or consent.
Material Theories of Whiteness
Whereas discursive approaches to whiteness theorizing
emphasize the power of ideas and symbols to shape our
perceptions of race, material approaches to whiteness insist on
the structural character of white power and privilege. From
such perspectives, it is not a question merely of the widespread
perception of whiteness as normative or superior that is
at issue but of the material inequality that characterizes race
relations in our society. People of color are systematically
excluded from the very real power, privileges, and entitlements
attached to whiteness. In general, whites have access to more
education, better-paying jobs, and a wider choice in housing
than do people of color. As a group, whites also have better
access to policies and programs that support their interests,
including bank loans, insurance, health benefits, and police
protection from physical violence. Supposedly, the arrangements
that organize access to material goods are referenced strictly
to individual merit; in fact, however, they systematically give
preference to whites.
Of course, not all whites enjoy the same privileges.
Depending on one's class, gender, sexuality, nationality,
religion, and ethnicity, whiteness may be wielded quite
differently. Both discourse and material whiteness theories
emphasize the multiplicity of whiteness. Discursive approaches
to whiteness address the constant shifting of the discourse to
reposition whiteness as normative or superior; structurally
oriented theories point to the multiple material forms that
white privilege may take. As Alcoff (1998) notes, the
privileges of whiteness have always been "differentially
distributed" in accordance with "class, gender, sex, ethnicity,
age, and able-bodiedness" (p. 9). For most men, she observes,
white privilege has meant getting a job, whereas for many
middle- and upper-class women white privilege has meant not
having to work.
Most commonly, material or structurally oriented whiteness
analyses focus on the ways in which whiteness is fractured by
class divisions, leading to continual "rearticulations,
representations, [and] reinterpretations of the meaning of race"
(Winant, 1997, p. 40). Howard Winant's chapter in Off
White offers an excellent example of such a structurally
oriented analysis. Although "the deep structures of white
privilege" have not been destroyed by the post-civil rights
era's emphasis on racial equality, Winant says, the recognition
of "counterclaims on behalf of the racially excluded and
subordinated" has left white identities in a state of anxiety,
confusion, and contradiction (p. 41). The "new politicization
of whiteness" can be seen in the variety of "white racial
projects" being pursued in the U.S. (p. 42): these include the
projects of the far right, the new right, neoconservatives,
neoliberals, and the "new abolitionists." (Note 5)
According to Winant, only the last-named group
identified with David Roediger (1994) and with Ignatiev and
Garvey (1996)actively problematizes the privileges of
whiteness or reinterprets social power relations from a
standpoint that critiques the social construction of that
privilege. Yet insofar as the project of the new abolitionists
involves eradicating rather than rearticulating whiteness,
Winant (1997) suggests, it reflects a limited understanding of
whiteness. Racism cannot be overcome by getting rid of
whiteness; instead, whiteness must be given new character and
new meaning. "Like any other complex of beliefs and practices,
'whiteness' is imbedded in a highly articulated social structure
and system of significations; rather than trying to repudiate
it, we shall have to rearticulate it." Rejecting the notion of
whiteness as nothing more than an ideaand thus something
that can be abandoned "by a mere act of political will"
(p. 48)Winant suggests that we need to address the work that
whiteness constructions do in maintaining race and class
privilege. We have to "reinterpret the meaning of whiteness in
such a way that it no longer has the power to impede class
alliances" (p. 49).
While the materialist discussion of the different ways in
which white privilege manifests itself is often illuminating, a
few of the chapters in Off White seem to insist on the
fractured character of whiteness simply as a way to downplay the
authors' own white privilege. Such authors invoke whiteness
theorizing primarily in order to discredit it, displacing the
question of whiteness by complexifying it. Part of the
argument, in such cases, is that whiteness cannot be understood
in essentializing terms but must be weighed against concurrent
experiences of marginalization: one is never just white; one
is white and working-class or white and female or white and gay,
for example. In and of itself, problematizing whiteness as a
unilateral category is not self-indulgent. Seizing upon a
falsely monolithic reading of whiteness specifically in order to
discredit it, though, seems to serve no other purpose than to
absolve a particular author of any complicity in white
privilege. As Gloria Anzaldúa (1990) has written, "Often
whitefeminists [sic] want to minimize racial difference by
taking comfort in the fact that we are all women and/or lesbians
and suffer similar sexual-gender oppressions" (p. xxi).
Whatever other forms of oppression whites may experience,
however, our whiteness still needs to be addressed as a source
of privilege. "While whiteness is clearly shaped by sexuality,
religion, and class," as Becky Thompson and her colleagues
(1997) acknowledge in their chapter, we cannot call upon "being
lesbian, or Jewish, or survivors of sexual abuse as a way to
distance ourselves from being white and the unearned privileges
we have been granted along the way" (p. 359).
Because whites want to avoid being associated with
oppressiveness, they are often tempted to draw attention to any
number of other modifiers that define them. We are not so much
white, we say, as Italian or Jewish or working-class. Analyzing
her own defensiveness about being identified as white, Faye
Crosby (1997) notes that she feels compelled to complicate the
category of whiteness by bringing to bear other aspects of her
identity: "middle-aged," "middle-class," "divorced," and being
of mixed heritage"a Protestant midwesterner (father) and a
Jewish French colonialist (mother)." This "rush toward
complexity," Crosby suggests, is a function of whites'
discomfort with the term "white" (p. 182). When we choose to
label ourselves as woman or teacher or mother (or lesbian, gay,
straight, middle-class, Northeastern, or Southwestern), by
contrast, we usually do not feel a comparable need to modify the
self-definition with the term "white."
However reassuring our modified categories are to those of
us who are white, they don't address how others see us.
Remembering when she first "had to identify with white people,"
an anti-racist, white activist describes an encounter with an
African-American woman who asked her, "Why are your people
teaching your children to hate me?" The question came as a
shock: "I don't think most [white] people ever think about
other white people as 'my people.'" Her first reaction was to
think that the people in question"those white people in
South Boston"were not her people. "First of all, they were
Irish and I am Italian, so we don't have to own them." But she
came to "realize that they are my people" (Thompson et al.,
1997, p. 359)and that she needed "to be able to explain to
people in my community that white supremacy and its ideology
have screwed us up" (p. 362). Claiming her whiteness meant that
she was able to address other whites as potential anti-racist
alliesto take an activist stance from a "we" position,
rather than addressing other whites as racist in a way that she
herself was not.
To the uneducated (or mis-educated) eye, structural forms
of privilege are usually invisible. Embedded in standardized
tests, college admissions requirements, teacher competency
exams, rank and tenure policies, drug laws, police procedures,
urban and suburban taxation practices, bank and insurance
policies, hiring patterns, and social security laws, for
example, structural forms of privilege appear impartial to those
who benefit from them. Since these policies and practices
appear fair to those who are best served by them, any attempt to
correct for bias in the policies and practices will appear
inherently discriminatoryhence the furious white,
middle-class (and often male) backlash against affirmative action. It
is when ideological and structural forms of racism meet that the
latter are most likely to be visible. Combined
materialist/discursive analyses of whiteness address issues such
as how structural white privilege is protected by white
discourses and how racist discourses are protected by colorblind
institutional structures.
Combined Materialist/Discursive Approaches
Among the important contributions of Off White are
the chapters that reveal both the ideological and the
institutional workings of whiteness, making visible the bias in
what may appear to be fair and impartial ways of handling racial
conflict. While few of the institutional analyses offered in
Off White explicitly take up the theoretical paradigms
set forth in the whiteness literature, they provide detailed
analyses of just how whiteness operates as a normalizing
principle. Playing by the rules, they suggest, tends to
reinscribe whiteness as the norm. By examining institutional
responses both to white racism and to solidarity initiatives
taken by people of color, these analyses show us what whites
(and occasionally people of color) may have to gain by insisting
on white values as generic values. Virginia Chalmers's (1997)
discussion of race dynamics at a predominantly white private
school, for example, demonstrates how the insistence on
progressive, anti-racist values such as openness and social
harmony was used as a mechanism to prevent people of color from
organizing amongst themselves to meet their children's needs,
while a case study focusing on a year-long racial conflict at
the University of Alaska Fairbanks (Gilmore, Smith, & Kairaiuak,
1997) reveals how the administration's bureaucratic response to
white racism alienated the Alaska Native community.
In the University of Alaska Fairbanks case, controversy
erupted over a professor's suggestion that Native students were
being given inflated grades so that they could graduate.
Adopting a "rational" policy of disinterested "attempts to sort
out the 'facts,'" the University gave credence to the white
professor's slander by allowing the question to be entertained
as worthy of study for almost a year. Although in the end there
was no evidence to support the claim that Native students were
being given inflated grades, the University's bureaucratic
stance put the Native communityrather than the professor
making the racist claimon the defensive. Institutional
analyses such as these show us how, even in the absence of ill
intent or overt discrimination, seemingly fair, impartial, and
colorblind procedures may lend support to discourses or policies
that are overtly racist. (Note 6)
Another chapter intertwining structural with discursive
analyses focuses more heavily on the discursive side, addressing
the ways in which white, working-class men symbolically
compensate for their loss of privilege in the 1990s. Because
new economic conditions have substituted lower-paying service
jobs for traditionally "masculine" working-class jobs, Lois
Weis, Amira Proweller, and Craig Centrie (1997) argue, white,
working-class men are unable to provide the same "family wage"
that their fathers and grandfathers did or to claim
"their once-certain advantage over white women and women and men of color"
(p. 211). Rather than blame elite decision-makers "for the
relocation of industries, closing of industries, and so forth"
(p. 214), however, these men blame people of color, attributing
their embattled economic position to people of color who have
unfairly taken "their" jobs. Drawing on white discourses about
affirmative action and welfare allows white, working-class men
to position themselves as deserving people, in contrast to
people of color. On the one hand, working-class people of color
who have jobs are said to have secured them unfairly (through
so-called quotas); on the other hand, people of color who
don't have jobs are characterized as welfare cheats who
exploit the system. In contrast to both people of color who
have jobs, then, and those who don't, white,
working-class men emphasize their own moral superiority.
Psychological Theories of Whiteness
Some but by no means all of the psychological work in
whiteness theory is consistent with discursive and materialist
approaches. Although psychologically oriented work focuses on
the personal identity of whites rather than the social
construction of whiteness, psychological approaches that
recognize racism as systemic and that acknowledge whites'
investment in whiteness are consistent with discourse and
material theories of whiteness. On the other hand,
psychological approaches that focus on individuals unlearning
racist patterns, and thereby leaving racism behind, make
assumptions about the nature of racism that are very different
from the assumptions found in the socially oriented literature.
(Note 7)
In psychological approaches that focus on the need to
abandon behaviors that privilege whiteness, whiteness is
recognized as leading to ethnic bias and ignorance but is not
addressed as a privilege that whites have reasons to protect.
Alcoff (1998) describes Judy Katz's (1978) sensitization
approach to whiteness, for example, as ignoring the ways in
which whiteness serves the material interests of whites.
Throughout Katz's White Awareness, says Alcoff (1998),
"racism is portrayed as a kind of macro-agent with its own
agenda, operating separately from white people" (p. 12).
Although Katz sees racism as debilitating to whites both
intellectually and psychologically, she ignores its political
and moral character, making "no reference to exploitation or the
need for a redistribution of resources." Racism for her is
simply "a psychological pathology that can be solved through
behavior modification" (p. 13). (Note 8)
By contrast, psychologist Janet Helms (1992)known for
her stage theory of healthy white developmentpays
considerable attention to the connections between white identity
and social and institutional privilege. Although organizing her
discussion around whites' personal growth and emphasizing the
need for whites to "actively . . . increase the racial
diversity" in their lives "as a way to learn and grow from such
experiences" (p. 87), Helms does not regard anti-racism as
merely a personal stance. Whiteness as Helms defines it has
been institutionalized as a supposedly generic perspective that
privileges whites. To dismantle the white bias in conventional
questions like "Can fairness in education, hiring, and promotion
be accomplished without quotas?", Helms recasts them in terms
that draw attention to the historical privileging of whiteness.
The correct version of this question, Helms indicates, would be:
"Can fairness in education, hiring, and promotion be
accomplished without ending White privilege?" (p. 80).
Theorists drawing on Helms's stage theory of white identity
have not always retained her political emphasis, however. In
particular, Helms's unfortunate description of the fully healthy
white person as "nonracist" (p. 87), implying that the mature
white person is no longer affected by racism, seems to have been
embraced by other theorists as a promise that really good
whites, once they understand racism, can simply leave it behind.
As described by Helms (1992), Carter (1997), and others, the
stage theory of white growth in racial awareness and acceptance
traces a trajectory that culminates in whites' ability to
embrace an identity that is comfortable with all colors,
including whiteness. In effect, this view of whiteness is an
extension of mainstream multiculturalism, in that it puts all
cultures and colors on an equal footing, embracing all without
privileging any. By contrast, socially oriented approaches to
whiteness theorizing emphasize the socially constructed
character of whiteness: according to these analyses, we cannot
escape the conditions that define whiteness, but we can try to
change the conditions.
Although the institutional, structural, and discursive
analyses usually identified with whiteness theory had already
made a considerable impact by the time that Off White was
published in 1997, quite a number of the psychologically
oriented chapters in Off White appear uninformed by that
literature. Many of these essays rely upon theoretical tools
drawn from the older tradition of "chilly classroom climate"
analyses to document the ways in which the pervasive
androcentrism, sexism, heterosexism, racism, ethnocentrism, and
elitism of the academy serve to silence, devalue, intimidate,
and exclude students and faculty from outside the dominant
groups. Helpful though such illustrations of racial bias can
be, they are not new framings of the issues. (Note 9) The study
of whiteness is more than the naming of clearly racist
practices. Theorizing whiteness means deconstructing the
framework by means of which even seemingly neutral and
non-racist practices serve to privilege whites (and occasionally
a few people of color).
Off-Whiteness Theorizing in Off White
Some chapters in Off White not only fail to grasp
the distinctiveness of whiteness theorizing but confuse the
project of deconstructing whiteness with liberal pluralism. One
essay, for example, ends with the hope that we will "examine our
viewpoints and the possibility that other viewpoints not
only exist but have merit" (Jones, 1997, p. 257; emphasis in
original). Whiteness theories, however, are by no means content
with acknowledging other points of viewlet alone with the
mere acknowledgement that other points of view might
possibly have merit. By discrediting the normative
status of whiteness, whiteness theories actually undercut
liberal pluralism's commitment to accepting multiple viewpoints,
for they undermine whiteness's own claim to being a coherent
point of view.
In addition to rejecting the liberal pluralist conception
of whiteness as simply one point of view among many, whiteness
theorists reject the notion of whiteness as a raceless category
to which other races may, in the name of colorblindness, be
assimilated. Yet one of the psychologically oriented chapters
in Off White relies on just such a notion, arguing that
the solution to racism is to effect recategorizations of racial
identification such that whites include blacks in the "we"
category. "When recategorization changes 'Us and Them' to
'We,'" these authors report, "outgroup members are treated more
favorably" (Gaertner, Dovidio, Banker, Rust, Nier, Mottola, &
Ward, 1997, p. 176). Whites, in other words, demonstrate less
biased attitudes towards non-whites when they see the latter as
members of their own group, whether the "we" group in question
is a sports team, a cooperative learning group in the classroom,
or simply the category "Americans." For example,
white San Francisco Bay residents who
identified themselves more strongly as
Americansa more inclusive group identitythan
as caucasians had more positive
attitudes towards policies intended to
benefit disadvantaged black citizens. (pp.
176-177) (Note 10)
But in recycling colorblind we-ness as the solution to racism,
such an analysis entirely ignores one of the central lessons of
whiteness theoriesnamely, that whiteness serves as the
unacknowledged norm by which "we-ness" is measured.
When whiteness is the norm, non-whites are by definition
not-like-us. Creating occasions when, contextually, certain
non-whites appear to be "just like us" (in the classroom or on a
soccer team) does nothing to dismantle the view that who "we"
are is a reasonable reference point for judging others.
Ironically, insofar as whites can point to occasions when they
experience non-whites as "just like us," they may lose their
awareness of the many ways in which racism structures who "we"
are. The problem of racism thus seems to recede. As one of the
structurally and discursively oriented essays in Off
White points out, whites in a largely white neighborhood
often will not object to families of color who live among them
if the "families are considered settled." Particular people of
color, in such cases, will be considered "just like us" (Weis et
al., 1997, p. 220). But this acceptance of particular people of
color does not alter the white commitment to keeping other
people of color out of the neighborhood.
Admitting outsiders to friendship may actually serve to
bolster the racist's case that he judges people as individuals,
not by color. Insofar as a white person can say (or at least
think) that "some of my best friends are black" or "some of my
best friends are Jewish," she is confirmed in her status as a
non-prejudiced person. Having one or two friends in "the other"
group is by no means inconsistent, however, with fearing or
hating everyone else in the group. Not a few loyal members of
the Nazi party helped Jewish friends escape Germany
occasionally at some risk to themselves. This willingness to
help one exceptional friend does not mean that the Nazis in
question were not also racist. While firmly believing in the
inferiority of Jews, they were able to see their own friends as
more deserving or as exceptions to the racial norm. Here, the
very status of exceptionality confirms the norm as normative.
The argument that recategorizing "'Us and Them' to 'We'"
allows "outgroup members [to be] treated more favorably" not
only tells us nothing new, it tells us nothing at all promising
about the future of anti-racism. The comfortable conviction
that whites can overcome their racism by assimilating "them" to
"us" assumes that the problem with blackness or brownness lies
in its difference from whiteness; in refusing to
recognize that difference, colorblindness negates the negativity
of blackness and brownness. Color, then, is still a problem
but only if one notices it. Colorblindness means refusing to
see others as any different from oneself: one looks at others
and sees oneself. Elizabeth Spelman (1988) calls this pattern
of racial assimilation "boomerang perception." During her
upbringing, Spelman says, "white children like me got early
training in boomerang perception when we were told by
well-meaning white adults that Black people were just like us
never, however, that we were just like Blacks" (p. 12). The
difficulty with the assimilationist solution to racism is that
it never questions the ground of racial meaning-making. Just as
treating a woman as an honorary man confirms maleness as the
highest value, treating non-whites as honorary whites assumes
the normative status of whiteness. Extending whiteness to
others reinscribes whiteness as the norm. It assumes that
racism is a problem connected to blackness or brownness, so that
blackness and brownness must be erased before racism will
disappear. Yet if whiteness gains its preferred and normative
status only by contrast to blackness or brownness, it is
discursively impossible to extend whiteness to everyone. The
racial hierarchy built into the white/other dichotomy means that
whiteness only retains its value as normative insofar as there
exist others who can be identified as not-white.
In more or less bracketing the ways in which
institutionalized race relations and discourses of whiteness are
linked to whites' sense of themselves as white, much of the
psychological theorizing of whiteness in Off White skirts
the complexities of white racial identity. Because these
chapters tend to focus on affirming the possibility of being a
"good" white person, they are forced to isolate the person from
the cultural and institutional context. Ironically, then, the
very focus on whiteness for anti-racist purposes may in the end
lend itself to a fetishization of "good" whiteness that obscures
the systematic relation of whiteness to oppression.
Off White as Overview
Despite some excellent work on the part of individual
contributors, Off White makes only a very modest
contribution to the academic literature. Less useful as a
reference book than it might have been, Off White has no
index and is careless with regard to references (including, in
many cases, missing, incomplete, or erroneous notes and
references). Some of the book's limitations are a matter of
presentation. The writing, for example, is uneven. Some of the
chapters are admirably clear, but others are merely workmanlike,
and a few are embarrassingly pretentious. Many of the essays
despite their notable brevityare also needlessly repetitive.
If, to include all thirty-two chapters, some needed to be
shortened, it would have been better to eliminate the internal
padding rather than to cut whole sections out, as seems to have
occurred in cases where the essays abruptly shift gears,
introducing new points without any indication of how these
points relate to the preceding analysis. In a number of essays,
key ideas and arguments are mentioned but not theorized, and I
was left wondering whether the authors had not bothered to
develop these points or if, instead, those sections had been cut
for the sake of space. Although the editors do not mention that
any of the chapters are shortened versions of essays already
published elsewhere, this seems to be the case for at least some
of them, and may help to explain why those chapters end abruptly
rather than coming to closure.
The purposes that the collection is meant to serve are
unclear. One declared purpose of Off White is "to fill
th[e] space" left by scholarship that avoids scrutinizing
whiteness (Fine, Powell, Weis, & Wong, 1997, p. viii). Yet it
is hard to see how any one book could be expected to fill a gap
so huge. Given that whiteness has enjoyed a normative status in
countless books and articles published over the past several
centuries, the space for critiquing whiteness would seem to be
larger than what could be filled by one book. There is simply
too much left to be reframed and retheorized.
A second announced purpose of the collection is to
demonstrate "the urgency, richness, and necessity of studying
whiteness," opening the field for new, "provocative theory and
research" (Fine et al., 1997, p. ix). Yet at the same time that
the editors argue for further inquiry into whiteness, they
suggest that "maybe this should be the last book on whiteness."
The curious choice to open the field to new research only to at
once close it again springs from a pivotal misunderstanding of
the project of whiteness theorizing. Rather than pursuing
whiteness theorizing any further, the editors say, we must "get
back to the work of understanding and dismantling the stratified
construction of race/colors, rather than [deconstructing] one
group at a time" (p. xii). Whiteness theorizing, however, does
not represent one stage in some serial deconstruction of racial
groups, with whites just happening to precede all other groups
in the line-up. Rather, whiteness theories reveal the ways in
which whiteness organizes the perception of other races
as deviant, thereby providing the lens through which we can
understand the very concepts of race and racial stratification.
Given the editors' misunderstanding of the central purpose
of whiteness theorizing, it is not surprising that the book
lacks a clear connection to the field it is meant to introduce
and then leave behind. Indeed, the editors' preface obscures
the status of the field as a field of theory and research,
seeming to suggest that the editors of Off White had to
more or less invent whiteness theorizing on their own. "While
the analytic study of whiteness defines, for all of us, both our
work and intimate lives, we have found ourselves with few
intellectual resources upon which to rely" (Fine et al., 1997,
p. ix). Although the editors name a handful of authors who have
influenced them, they fail to acknowledge that whiteness theory
was already a flourishing field by the time that Off
White was published. David Roediger's The Wages of
Whiteness had exploded onto the research scene in 1991,
followed by the Toni Morrison's (1992) highly influential
Playing in the Dark and Ruth Frankenberg's (1993)
important and much-cited White Women, Race Matters: The
Social Construction of Whiteness. So vital a field of
inquiry was whiteness theorizing by 1997 that, in the same year
that Off White was published, at least six major books
appeared on the topic, along with any number of articles. And
this is to mention only the contemporary literature that goes
under the name of whiteness theory. Since the earliest part of
the century, Latina/s, American Indians, African Americans, and
other people of color have consistently challenged the normative
status claimed for whiteness. The barest acquaintance with the
work of W. E. B. Du Bois (1903/1990), Carter G. Woodson
(1933/1972), Vine Deloria (1969), and Cherríe Moragu and Gloria
Anzaldúa (1981/1983) would reveal that the critique of whiteness
is not new.
Failing as it does to locate itself in either the classic
or the more recent scholarship on whiteness, Off White
taken as a wholeis disappointing. Newcomers to the field
will find it difficult to know which of the book's thirty-two
chapters take up contested points, which introduce new ideas,
and which assume the very frameworks of analysis that whiteness
theorists specifically reject. Since few of the authors argue
for a particular conception of whiteness, moreover, even
important insights tend to be embedded in less than satisfying
analyses. Some of the chapters offer solid analyses of
whiteness, but relatively few make a new contribution or move us
beyond previous work in the area. Some merely repeat or
summarize insights that are commonplace in the whiteness
literature; others, adopting a conventional liberal view of
whiteness, unknowingly work against the conceptualization of
race found in whiteness theories. Not only does the editorial
decision not to provide any overview of whiteness theory mean
that readers who are new to the study of whiteness will have no
way to determine what relation the chapters bear to the existing
literature, but it renders a disservice to the authors whose
work is represented in the collection. Without an editorial
framework that clarifies what is at stake in the book, even the
strongest chapters hang in a theoretical limbo.
Turning the Whiteness Lens on Anti-Racist Practices in Education
Buried in the confusing organization of Off White is
a scattering of essays that speak importantly to the pressing
issues now facing education. In both pedagogy and research, far
more work needs to be done to help us rethink the whiteness of
our educational practices. A number of the essays in Off
White focus on schools as institutions, and others suggest
in passing that "education is a critical site" wherein struggles
over "moral affiliation" are enacted (McCarthy et al., 1997, p.
234), but only a handful specifically address the pedagogical
implications of whiteness theorizing. Among these is Crosby's
(1997) provocative chapter noting the limitations of an
anti-racist pedagogy that positions the teacher self-righteously
against the student. "For those who study affirmative action,
the attitudes of angry and frightened White males can provoke
some impatience," she recognizes. She offers the insights of
whiteness theorizing as a corrective to this us/them
positioning. "To end the impatience and become sympathetic with
aspects of the resistance to affirmative action, I need only
remember how privilege has blinded me too" (p. 185).
In a similar vein, Becky Thompson (1997) notes that white
anti-racist activists cannot take the position of "experts" or
"morality agents" but must approach other whites as potential
allies. Because racism in our society is so unrelenting, it is
easy for white anti-racist activists to get discouraged. "I
really struggle to remember that we are all scared," one of
Thompson's colleagues says. "Sometimes I get caught up in
believing that this other white person is really different,
really 'other,' really racist" (p. 362). As another colleague
points out, though, "they don't even know they're doing it."
Seen as ignorance, racism offers "room for growth" (p. 361). In
not focusing on racist errors to be corrected but instead
recognizing possibilities for growth, such approaches restore a
student-centered ethic to progressive education, and resist the
temptations to authoritative teaching found in many "liberatory"
approaches to critical pedagogy. (Note 11)
In research, too, as Aída Hurtado and Abigail Stewart
(1997) point out in their chapter, conventionally liberatory
methods may prove inadequate. "Analytic tools and research
methods that helped us understand systems and experiences of
oppression may not be as appropriate for understanding
privilege" (p. 298). For example, they say, liberatory
approaches to research that privilege the voices of the
oppressed, keeping authorial commentary to a minimum, are meant
to empower those whose perspectives have been excluded from
academic research. Applied to the analysis of the racist views
of those in power, however, the voice-centered method would have
very different consequences, for it gives greater scope to the
articulation of racism.
Indeed, the voice-centered convention may be problematic
even when used to affirm those who speak out against oppression.
For example, Michael Apple's (1997) chapter in Off White
borrows an analysis from a "close friend and former student" in
an unnamed "Asian country for which I have a good deal of
fondness" (p. 121), to provide a non-U.S.-centered account of
why there are "no schools, no teachers, no hospitals, no
infrastructure" in this country. In the words of his friend,
"There's no schools because so many folks like cheap french
fries" (p. 123). Under the conventional terms of progressive,
liberatory research, Apple's use of his friend's story is
unproblematic. From the perspective of whiteness theories,
however, approaches to "collaboration" and "representation" in
which the author speaks for the research subject look far more
problematic, since they betray academic scholarship's investment
in rationalized and mediated representation. In principle,
approaches like the one Apple adopts allow an author to serve as
a sympathetic or even invisible mouthpiece for those who
otherwise might not have access to academic forms of
representation. Taking up others' stories for one's own
critical purposes, though, raises concerns about cooptation.
Even in the interests of solidarity against racism,
colonization, and xenophobia, borrowing others' stories raises
questions about whether academics are constructing and
maintaining their own intellectual and cultural authority at the
expense of those for whom they claim to speak. As Ellsworth
(1997) points out in a somewhat different connection, academics
retain the right (even if they give it away) to have "the last
word" (p. 265). Of course, the writer also gets the academic
credit and the intellectual visibility.
In effect, such research involves a laundered form of
whiteness. Good intentions do not absolve authors of the
privilege they assume in such transactions. Even if an author
takes over someone else's story to protect the person's
anonymity and to safeguard him from harassment, the problem of
implicitly white authority remains, because the mechanism by
which authority is granted to the story is specifically
academic: it is through the author's expertise that the story
is given legitimacy. In legitimating others' stories,
whiteness-as-academic expertise launders its own cultural
origins, bleaching out and rendering invisible the mechanism by
which it manufactures cultural capital.
Psychologically and socially oriented whiteness theories
offer different advantages in problematizing the whiteness of
our pedagogical and research practices. Depending on the
particular whiteness project, reflecting on one's personal
privileges as a white person might not always be useful, except
insofar as such reflection undercuts the temptation to posture
as a "good white," a white person who gets itas in the
pedagogical examples mentioned earlier. Reflecting on the
institutionalized whiteness of one's academic position
and intellectual practice, on the other hand, may prove to be an
indispensable dimension of whiteness theorizing for
intellectuals of all colors. (Note 12) Whiteness theorizing,
after all, is not just about people of color being marginalized
and/or exploited; the older structural theories already
acknowledged that. Rather, whiteness theorizing concerns the
particular mechanisms by which whitesincluding anti-racist
theoristsare privileged. Most importantly, whiteness
theories address the ways in which white privilege is actively
maintained and reconstituted. Whiteness theories are
positioned to deconstruct these mechanisms, but the question is
whether they can deconstruct their own as well as other
culturally and institutionally white meaning-making practices.
Alternative approaches, Hurtado and Stewart (1997) suggest,
might include involving "individuals with different views," two
or more "interviewers from different social locations," and
"focus groups [ . . . or] other participants" reflecting
"multiple perspectives" (p. 309). (Some of these methods are
taken up in the chapter by Lykes and Mallona [1997].) While
such methods are worth exploring, they risk falling back upon a
liberal pluralist paradigm. The inclusion of multiple
perspectives is meant to counteract white hegemonybut
liberal pluralism, as discussed earlier, has proved an
inadequate corrective to normalizing constructions of whiteness.
In "The White Girl in Me, the Colored Girl in You, and the
Lesbian in Us," Medria Connolly and Debra Noumair (1997) offer
an approach more distinctively inflected by whiteness theory.
Accepting whiteness theories' insight that "the 'not me' and the
'not us' are used to define 'me' and 'us'," they reexamine "me"
and "us" by acknowledging those aspects of themselves that the
binary language of race and sexuality automatically excludes (p.
322). For example, the language of racial authenticity may cast
a black woman who is successful in academia as "a wanna be white
girl" (p. 326), while heteronormative constructions of the good
white girl specifically exclude "erotic and powerful" forms of
agency (p. 330). In order to claim both/and constructions of
the self, the authors focus on those "aspects of the self or the
group that are disowned or rejected" (p. 322). The result is an
engaging and provocative reconceptualization of both "we" and
"me."
Other methods may serve well in other educational whiteness
projects. Both standpoint approaches and deconstructive
analyses, for example, help to illuminate the whiteness of
particular discourses. But while these and other methods are
often used to good effect in Off White, they cannot be
assumed to be free of their own forms of privilege. For the
most part, in any case, the authors represented in Off
White do not interrogate the limitations of existing
methodologies with respect to whiteness theorizing. Nor do they
question their own academic privilege; perhaps they assume that
writing on behalf of an anti-racist project speaks for itself.
As Elizabeth Ellsworth's (1997) powerful essay points out,
however, "antiracist scholarship is never only antiracist" (p.
263). Its anti-oppressive character never obliterates its
scholarly character. However well-intentioned it may be, white
anti-racist scholarship is still "scholarshipgoverned by
rules that . . . produce and insure its own" investments in
whiteness (p. 263). And because scholarly conventions are
rooted in mainstream institutions, the scholarly character of
whiteness theorizing risks reinscribing whiteness into the very
discourses that the theories are meant to interrupt.
Ellsworth's (1997) own recommendation is for whiteness
theorists and pedagogues to "metacommunicate about how academic
discourses and writing" profit from and reinscribe the
privileging of whiteness. "What can paralyze an academic's
ability to respond to racist uses of whiteness," she says, is an
"inability or unwillingness 'to leave the field'" or to
challenge the binaries that constrain what counts as an
intelligible response to racism (p. 264). Refusing the academic
authority to challenge racism from a position of knowledge means
problematizing what we do as we do it: "Academe must be made to
comment on itself directly" (p. 268) through metadiscourse. Yet
Ellsworth's use of the passive voice here is rather telling, for
who is to do the making? She herself, in fact, seems less than
sanguine about this reflexive approach. As a result of working
through these ideas, she says, "I want to leave academe" (p.
268). It is not clear, however, how leaving academe would solve
the problem of reinscribing whiteness in challenges to
whiteness. White art, white administrative politics, white
journalism, white humor, white counter-cultural activism, and
white literature, for example, are not free of their own
whiteness-reinscribing conventions.
In appealing to metadiscourse as a solution to the
whiteness of scholarly theorizing about race, moreover,
Ellsworth seems to revert to a faith in intellectualism as
offering the most reliable challenge to racism. Even if we do
not take Derrida at his word, that there is no
"hors de texte"personally, I am not inclined to see the recent Texas and
Wyoming lynchings of a black man and a gay man as "texts"; I
call those real events, real outrages, real injusticesit
seems fair to say that there is no such thing as a discourse
that is somehow outside of discourse. Metadiscourses are not
more objective than other discourses. They cannot save us from
the particularity of any particular discourse. One discourse
can interrupt another, no doubt, but no discourse can set us
"straight."
In any case, white supremacist power relations are not
simply a matter of how we think about whiteness but of how laws
and institutions support those ways of thinking. While the
critique of whiteness is an important contribution to racial
activism, its power is limited if it is confined to more of the
same kinds of descriptions and analyses at which academics are
already adept. If we recall that problematizing whiteness is
not a new projectthat people of color have done so for
yearsthen we are forced to recognize that for white academics to
problematize whiteness is simply to take the project into the
academy. It is an academic project, addressed to scholarly
concernsnamely, rethinking what we know. And we have yet to
rethink what it means to think in ways that might reconstruct or
radically rearrange social practices, institutional commitments,
or material relations.
Conclusion
For too long, well-meaning whites have expected people of
color to do the work of unraveling racism. Unfortunately, some
of the most successful educational interventions aimed at
challenging white privilege have been those that rely on having
people of color describe "their pain, vulnerabilities, and
strengths" (Zane, 1997, p. 349) as a way to engage whites in
transformative discussions. "The cost (and gain)" of such
"self- and group-disclosures," Nancie Zane says in her chapter
in Off White, still need to be explored. While for some
minority participants the experience is "cathartic," others feel
"emotionally drained and exposed," or feel that they are "'left
hanging' and 'used'" (p. 353). For most whiteness scholars,
however, the issues in such cases are already clear: whites
cannot look to people of color to teach them how not to be
racist. Following the urgings of scholars of color not to
"expect that people of color should teach you how to
behave non-oppressively" (Yamato, 1990, p. 23), the majority of whiteness
theorists have taken on the work of anti-racist learning as a
white initiative.
For many whiteness theorists, what being anti-racist means
is still under (re)construction. Not only do the structural and
discursive whiteness projects problematize several earlier
traditions in white anti-racism, but they problematize some of
the anti-racist recommendations of psychologically oriented
whiteness approaches, as well. Among the influential but
problematic recommendations now circulating is the argument
that, while whites cannot escape their whiteness, they can find
an honorable way to be white: they can be "allies" to people of
color. In Off White, for example, Sandra Lawrence and
Beverly Tatum (1997) suggest that "a more positive, less
guilt-inducing definition of . . . white identity" is one that enables
whites to think of themselves as "allies" (p. 338). Equating
this stance with the highest stage of Janet Helms's (1992)
six-stage white racial identity theory (also discussed in Robert
Carter's [1997] chapter), Lawrence and Tatum urge teachers to
create for themselves "a new identity, that of educator as ally,
an advocate for students of color, and a much-needed antiracist
role model for white students" (p. 341).
There is much to be said for such a stance. While it seems
excessive to describe the white person at this stage as having
"freed self from racism" (Carter, 1997, p. 205) and having
"abandon[ed] cultural, institutional, and personal racism" (p.
206)how does someone "abandon" institutional racism?
clearly whites who aspire to be allies actively refuse racism
and racial privilege insofar as that is possible. Among the
important advantages to the ally argument are its pedagogical
implications. Understandably, educators want to avoid giving
their students the message that whiteness is always and
everywhere bad. Offering white students and teachers the ally
option is likely to be more effective than offering them nothing
but critical tools, for it is difficult to accept one's white
identity if this means seeing oneself simply as an oppressor.
White guilt is usually counterproductive and, as our white
students like to remind us, whites can't help being white. From
a student-centered perspective, it is far from liberating to try
to build student understanding on the "deficit" of their own
racism. Yet assuring students that they can be allies or good
whites keeps our attention focused on white anxieties and white
value systems. It also tempts us with dichotomies that allow us
to differentiate absolutely between good and bad forms of
whiteness.
As Ellsworth (1997) points out, the ally position is
problematic both because an ally's "commitment, energy,
vigilance, interest, [and] ability" may flag at any time and
because allies, "positioned as helpers and legitimizers" of
people of color, bear a paternalistic relation to people of
color (p. 267). In effect, the position of ally reinscribes the
traditional white, mainstream moral economy whereby those in
positions of privilege gain moral credit for "helping" people of
color, while the latter, in struggling to survive, may be
positioned tragically or even nobly, but not morally. (Note 13)
Under the terms of the white, middle-class moral
economy, whites continue to hold themselves apart from questions
of race. Although racism is not "our" problem, we are prepared
to stand in solidarity with people of color. Addressing racism
thus becomes an act of benevolence towards people of color
rather than an act of responsibility on our own behalf.
A conversation reported in Off White brings this
point home. Jody, a white student, recalls what her brother's
girlfriend, Tashia, who is African American, said to her after
Tashia experienced racist treatment in a restaurant. When Jody
"want[ed] to tell people off," Tashia told her, "Don't do it for
me. If you're doin' it, make sure it's something you want to
say for yourself" (Rosenberg, 1997, p. 82). The lesson Tashia
teaches Jody is that anti-racism is not a favor white people do
for people of color. For many whites, this lesson may be a hard
one to learn. The notion that anti-racist work is "helping"
work, a way of being a "good white" person, of getting racial
"credit," has long been part of the moral make-up of benevolent
whiteness. Yet to the extent that appeals to the ally position
or other "nonracist" positions accept the conventional liberal
dichotomy between good (nonracist) whites and bad (racist)
whites, they continue to work within the terms set by the very
conceptions of individual morality and political innocence that
most whiteness theorists seek to challenge. Deconstructing
whiteness helps to problematize some of the values that
well-meaning whites may view as specifically moral responses to
racismincluding colorblindness, "blind" justice, and a
"helping" stance.
Until whites are willing to forego the helping-others
"credit" earned for anti-racist work and take it on as their own
work, the task undertaken by whiteness critics will not be
complete. "The challenge," as African-Canadian author Sherene
Razack (1998) argues, is to "build critical consciousness about
how we, as subjects, position ourselves as innocent through the
use of such markers of identity as the good activist" (p. 18).
In a racist society, there is no escape from racism: no one is
innocent. (Even the victims of racism are implicated in racism,
as the "color struck" politics within the African-American
community and the histories of black-on-black, brown-on-black,
black-on-brown, and brown-on-brown racism remind us.) The
temptation to be a "good white" assumes that we know what it is
to be a good white, but the only way we can know that is in
terms of where we are nowand where we are now is in the
midst of a racialized and racist situation. Anti-racist whites
can neither escape that situation nor entirely forego the
advantages that they gain from it; they can only work to
trouble and change the situation.
Rearticulating whiteness is an emergent project. We know
the racism of our whiteness in part through recourse to
particular methods of inquiry but in part also by our own
resistances to change and by our temptations to see ourselves in
particular racialized terms. A temptation for progressive
whites is to not only be a good white but to be
recognized as a good white. Identifying oneself as an
anti-racist ally or aspiring to a final stage of moral white
development, however, evades the problematic character of
whiteness. In a racist society, whiteness is an inherently
problematic position. The challenge for anti-racist whites is
not to become good whites in any of the ways that we now
recognize as good. The challenge, rather, is to become white in
ways that we cannot yet recognize, by changing institutions and
by changing the rules of the game that at present define the
good we know in terms of whiteness. (Note 14)
Notes
-
The large body of research challenging this assumption
makes it clear that white racism is alive and healthy;
nevertheless, the popular perception of white racism as a
fringe ideology persists. A recent contribution to the
research on white prejudice is the "mammoth, seven-volume
survey . . . sponsored by the Russell Sage Foundation .
. . and the Harvard University Multidisciplinary Program in
Inequality and Social Policy." Released in the fall of
1999, "The Multi-City Study of Urban Inequality" looked at
"9,000 households and 3,500 employers" in Boston,
Atlanta, Detroit, and Los Angeles. The study found white
racism to be "a pervasive influence at many levels,
manifesting itself in everything from highly segregated
housing to labor markets that prefer hiring some racial
groups over others." Ironically, the Associated Press
article summarizing the study avoided using the term
"racism."
Instead, it referred to "racial stereotypes and attitudes,"
"racial inequality," or, most often, simply "race" (Estrin,
1999, p. A1).
http://www.sltrib.com:80/1999/oct/10021999/nation_w/33605.htm
- See, for example, Kailin's (1999) discussion of the
comments that white teachers made about black students,
parents, teachers, and administrators in their district.
For their own part, white teachers in the progressive
school
district that Kailin studied thought racism was more or
less a non-issue. However, they regularly identified
African
Americans as racistusually when they did not support
white attitudes and disciplinary measures regarding black
students.
-
Winant (1997) and Giroux (1997) note that, in the new
racial politics of the nineties, many whites see themselves
as besieged. Insofar as whites feel threatened as whites,
they are made consciousness of their whiteness. Whiteness
is no longer invisible in some of the ways that it had
been, then; white privilege, however, remains invisible.
Indeed, the insistence on whiteness as an embattled
position renders white privilege even less visible.
- It is precisely the givenness of the context that is
at issue for whiteness theorists. Treating a situation as
given
skews our understanding of the moral actions and relations
at stake. When a situation is organized around
oppressive or unequal relations, we cannot address those
involved as if they merely happened to find
themselves in that context, but must see them as part of
the situation. A colorblind, individualistic morality that
distributes moral credit and blame to individuals as if
they were atomistic agents ignores the moral implications
of
individuals' shared situation, further privileging those
who are already privileged by that situation. (Of course,
this
analysis does not only apply to racialized situations.)
- Although Winant does not explain this term, it is a
reference to the periodical Race Traitor: A Journal of
the
New Abolitionism, which uses the slogan "Treason to
Whiteness is Loyalty to Humanity." The journal offers
tips on dismantling whiteness by refusing the privileges
attendant on whiteness. See Ignatiev and Garvey (1996).
- More traditional anti-racist theorizing calls our
attention either to overtly discriminatory rules (such as
Jim Crow
laws) or to discriminatory applications of otherwise
unproblematic legal, bureaucratic, and other rules.
Speaking to current evidence that the South is "turning
back the clock on voting rights" (Nixon, 1999, p. 11), a
recent article in The Nation described the federal
prosecution of fraudulently used absentee ballots
only in counties "affiliated with majority-black
groups" (Nixon, 1999, p. 14). In such analyses, what is at
stake is not the actual system of rules but the selective
appeal to such rules to intimidate black voters and thereby
limit blacks'but not whites'voting power. Such
analyses of racist practices perform a valuable and needed
function, but one quite different from that of the analyses
provided by structurally oriented whiteness theorists. The
latter make visible the bias in the rules themselves
specifically, rules that appear to be generic.
- Most psychological whiteness theorizing is grounded
in psychology as a discipline; however, other work
focusing
primarily on white identity would be grouped with the
psychological whiteness literature. Philosophical work
that
emphasizes the development of a white, anti-racist
character, for example, would fit under the
psychological rubric insofar as its emphasis is on who the
person is or is becoming. Some whiteness theorizing
bridges psychological and other traditions. To the extent
that the emphasis in Minnie Bruce Pratt's (1984) and
Peggy McIntosh's (1989) work is on self-reflection and
self-awareness regarding white privilege, for example,
their
analyses might be considered part of the psychological
strain in whiteness theorizing. Insofar as their work
focuses
on the social construction of whiteness, though, it would
be grouped with discourse and material theories of
whiteness.
- It should be noted, however, that Katz does address
various forms of institutional racism in her book. For
Katz,
institutional racism is a kind of cultural bias sedimented
into institutionalized practices. Although she does not
treat
institutional racism as part of a racial economy that
systematically favors white interests, she does recognize
that
racist assumptions and values are built into hiring
practices, IQ tests, and other institutionalized patterns.
Of course,
Katz's work predates the research now being identified as
whiteness theory. Since most of the mainstream literature
of the seventies displayed very little awareness of whites'
material investment in white privilege, it is not
surprising
that her version of healthy white identity should be
decontextualized from the social and institutional
conditions that
organize white privilege.
- In describing the analysis used in some of the
chapters as belonging to the older "chilly classroom
climate"
tradition, I do not mean to suggest that such analyses are
no longer useful. On the contrary, they remind us that the
distinctive pattern of exclusion that is the focus of such
analyses has by no means disappeared. However, since
Off White is offered to readers as a contribution to
whiteness theorizing, and since whiteness theorizing has
introduced new, distinctive tools of analysis, the chapters
using tools drawn from already-established traditions of
anti-racist theorizing make no real contribution to the
project at hand.
- Their use of the term "Caucasian" is in itself an
indication that the authors have not read whiteness theory.
Whiteness theorists specifically reject the
quasi-biological term "Caucasian." The term "white" highlights
the
socially constructed character of white identity.
- Some of the tensions between authoritative and
student-centered approaches to critical pedagogy are
explored in
Gitlin and Thompson (1995).
- A few of the privileging functions of scholarly
conventions of argumentation, description, and analysis are
discussed in Thompson (1998). Breaking out of these
conventions is by no means easy, and of course the present
essay does not itself break free of such conventions.
- At a Philosophy of Education Society meeting in New
Orleans in the spring of 1999, Nel Noddings pointed out
that focusing on which partner in a relationship gets
"moral credit"for example, the teacher or the
studentobscures the relational character of morality. It also
tends to concentrate our attention on how something
reflects on
us morally instead of on what needs to be done. Resisting
this analysis, Michael Slote argued that, ideally, one acts
morally in a relationship without being conscious of acting
morallyone cares spontaneously. Other
people, however, can evaluate one's actions as
praiseworthy. In my view, the position that insists on
praiseworthiness as the moral standard but hopes to
disguise the standard from moral agents is a sentimental
and
highly problematic view of morality. It institutes a
moral economy based on praiseworthy individual
action, for which one receives moral credit, but pretends
that the real motive for moral action is unrelated
to
any awareness of how "moral credit" is awarded. It is
significant that this is such a familiar stance in the
discourse
about white innocence and racism. According to that
discourse, whites are non-racistand get moral credit
for
their positionspecifically because they are oblivious
to racism as the context of action.
The emphasis on individual praiseworthiness is no less problematic
when applied to consciously anti-racist action. A moral economy that
grants "good whites" individual moral credit for being allies, for
example, obscures both the relational and the situational or systemic
character of racism. In effect, the "allies" stance treats racism as
something outside of white agents, something that they can join in
solidarity against, together with non-whites. But white racism is
not something apart from whiteness; it is part of the socially
constructed and maintained make-up of whiteness. In a racist
society, whites are situated by the institutionalized privileges of
whiteness in ways that they cannot undo by any act of will. This is
not to say that anti-racist whites are morally no different from
pro-racist whites. Certainly it is better to be anti-racist than to
be pro-racist. The point, however, is that a moral focus on blame
and merit tends to direct attention away from the political
conditions under which such blame and merit are allocated.
Anti-racist efforts, if they are not to characterize whites as
helpers who are somehow outside the problem of racism, cannot
identify anti-racist whites as "good whites" or allies. Instead,
they must position anti-racist whites as working on their own
situation and relationships. One of whiteness theories' most
important contributions to anti-racist activism may be in helping us
to conceptualize this moral stance.
- I would like to express my appreciation for the very
helpful readings I received on earlier drafts of this essay
from Bryan Brayboy, Ed Buendía, Aimee Howley, and Ivan Van
Laningham. I am also indebted to Eduardo Duarte,
Elizabeth Moje, Charise Nahm, and Harvey Siegel for
discussing particular points with me. For a discussion of
the
larger context of whiteness theorizing, see the companion
essay review published in Educational Studies, 30
(2): 141-160.
References
Alcoff, L. M. (1998). What should white people do?
Hypatia, 13, 3, 6-26.
Anzaldúa, G. (1990). Haciendo cara, una entrada. In G.
Anzaldúa (Ed.), Making face, making soul/Haciendo caras:
Creative and critical perspectives by women of color (pp. xv-
xxviii). San Francisco: Aunt Lute Foundation Books.
Apple, M. W. (1997). Consuming the other: Whiteness,
education, and cheap french fries. In M. Fine, L. Weis, L. C.
Powell, & L. M. Wong (Eds.), Off White: Readings on race,
power, and society (pp. 121-128). New York: Routledge.
Billig, M. (1997). Keeping the white queen in play. In
M. Fine, L. Weis, L. C. Powell, & L. M. Wong (Eds.), Off
White: Readings on race, power, and society (pp. 149-157).
New York: Routledge.
Carter, R. T. (1997). Is white a race? Expressions of
white racial identity. In M. Fine, L. Weis, L. C. Powell, & L.
M. Wong (Eds.), Off White: Readings on race, power, and
society (pp. 198-209). New York: Routledge.
Chalmers, V. (1997). White out: Multicultural
performances in a progressive school. In M. Fine, L. Weis, L.
C. Powell, & L. M. Wong (Eds.), Off White: Readings on race,
power, and society (pp. 66-78). New York: Routledge.
Connolly, M. L., & Noumair, D. A. (1997). The white girl
in me, the colored girl in you, and the lesbian in us: Crossing
boundaries. In M. Fine, L. Weis, L. C. Powell, & L. M. Wong
(Eds.), Off White: Readings on race, power, and society
(pp. 322-332). New York: Routledge.
Crosby, F. J. (1997). Confessions of an affirmative
action mama. In M. Fine, L. Weis, L. C. Powell, & L. M. Wong
(Eds.), Off White: Readings on race, power, and society
(pp. 179-186). New York: Routledge.
Deloria, V., Jr. (1969). Custer died for your sins:
An Indian manifesto. New York: Avon.
Du Bois, W. E. B. (1903/1990). The souls of black
folk. New York: Vintage.
Ellsworth, E. (1997). Double binds of whiteness. In M.
Fine, L. Weis, L. C. Powell, & L. M. Wong (Eds.), Off White:
Readings on race, power, and society (pp. 259-69). New
York: Routledge.
Estrin, R. (1999, October 2). Color matters: Race
remains entrenched in U. S. culture. The Salt Lake
Tribune, p. A1.
Fine, M., Powell, L. C., Weis, L., & Wong, L. M. (1997).
Preface. In M. Fine, L. Weis, L. C. Powell, & L. M. Wong
(Eds.), Off White: Readings on race, power, and society
(pp. vii-xii). New York: Routledge.
Foucault, M. (1980). Power/knowledge: Selected
interviews and other writings 1972-1977. Ed. C. Gordon.
(C. Gordon, L. Marshall, J. Mepham, & K. Soper, Trans.). New
York: Pantheon Books.
Frankenberg, R. (1993). White women, race matters: The
social construction of whiteness. Minneapolis: University
of Minnesota Press.
Gaertner, S. L., Dovidio, J. F., Banker, B. S., Rust, M.
C., Nier, J. A., Mottola, G. R., & Ward, C. M. (1997). Does
white racism necessarily mean antiblackness? Aversive racism
and prowhiteness. In M. Fine, L. Weis, L. C. Powell, & L. M.
Wong (Eds.), Off White: Readings on race, power, and
society (pp. 167-178). New York: Routledge.
Gilmore, P., Smith, D. M., & Kairaiuak, A. L. (1997).
Resisting diversity: An Alaskan case of institutional struggle.
In M. Fine, L. Weis, L. C. Powell, & L. M. Wong (Eds.), Off
White: Readings on race, power, and society (pp. 90-99).
New York: Routledge.
Giroux, H. A. (1997). Rewriting the discourse of racial
identity: Towards a pedagogy and politics of whiteness.
Harvard Educational Review, 67, 285-320.
Gitlin, A., & Thompson, A. (1995). Foregrounding politics
in action research. McGill Journal of Education, 30,
131-147.
Helms, J. E. (1992). A race is a nice thing to have:
A guide to being a white person or understanding the white
persons in your life. Topeka, KS: Content Communications.
Hurtado, A., & Stewart, A. J. (1997). Through the looking
glass: Implications of studying whiteness for feminist methods.
In M. Fine, L. Weis, L. C. Powell, & L. M. Wong (Eds.), Off
White: Readings on race, power, and society (pp. 297-311).
New York: Routledge.
Ignatiev, N., & Garvey, J. (Eds.). (1996). Race
traitor. New York: Routledge.
Jones, J. M. (1997). Whites are from Mars, O. J. is from
Planet Hollywood: Blacks don't support O. J. and whites just
don't get it. In M. Fine, L. Weis, L. C. Powell, & L. M. Wong
(Eds.), Off White: Readings on race, power, and society
(pp. 251-258). New York: Routledge.
Kailin, J. (1999). How white teachers perceive the
problem of racism in their schools: A case study in "liberal"
Lakeview. Teachers College Record, 100, 724-750.
Katz, J. H. (1978). White awareness: Handbook for
anti-racism training. Norman: University of Oklahoma
Press.
Kidder, L. H. (1997). Colonial remnants: Assumptions of
privilege. In M. Fine, L. Weis, L. C. Powell, & L. M. Wong
(Eds.), Off White: Readings on race, power, and society
(pp. 158-166). New York: Routledge.
Kohl, H. (1995). The story of Rosa Parks and the
Montgomery bus boycott revisited. In Should We Burn Babar?
Essays on Children's Literature and the Power of Stories
(pp. 30-56). New York: The New Press.
Lawrence, S. M., & Tatum, B. D. (1997). White educators
as allies: Moving from awareness to action. In M. Fine, L.
Weis, L. C. Powell, & L. M. Wong (Eds.), Off White: Readings
on race, power, and society (pp. 333-342). New York:
Routledge.
Lykes, M. B., & Mallona, A. (1997). Surfacing our-selves:
¿Gringa, whiteMestiza, brown? In M. Fine, L. Weis, L. C.
Powell, & L. M. Wong (Eds.), Off White: Readings on race,
power, and society (pp. 312-321). New York: Routledge.
McCarthy, C., Buendía, E., Mills, C., Meacham, S., Godina,
H., Wilson-Brown, C., Seferian, M., & Souchet, T. (1996). The
last rational men: Citizenship, morality, and the pursuit of
human perfection. In J. L. Kincheloe, S. R. Steinberg, & A. D.
Gresson III (Eds.), Measured lies: The bell curve examined
(pp. 251-264). New York: St. Martin's Press.
McCarthy, C., Rodriguez, A., Meecham, S., David, S.,
Wilson-Brown, C., Godina, H., Supryia, K. E. & Buendía, E.
(1997). Race, suburban resentment, and the representation of
the inner city in contemporary film and television. In M. Fine,
L. Weis, L. C. Powell, & L. M. Wong (Eds.), Off White:
Readings on race, power, and society (pp. 229-241). New
York: Routledge.
McIntosh, P. (1989, July/August). White privilege:
Unpacking the invisible knapsack. Peace and Freedom, 10-
12.
Moragu, C., & Anzaldúa, G. (Eds.). (1981/1983). This
bridge called my back: Writings by radical women of color. New
York: Kitchen Table/Women of Color Press.
Morrison, T. (1992). Playing in the dark: Whiteness
and the literary imagination. New York: Vintage: Random
House.
Nixon, R. (1999, November 15). Turning back the clock on
voting rights. The Nation, 269: 16, 11-17. [Available
online at
http://www.thenation.com/issue/991115/1115nixon.shtml.]
Pratt, M. B. (1984). Identity: Skin blood heart. In
E. Bulkin, M. B. Pratt, & B. Smith, Yours in struggle: Three
feminist perspectives on anti-Semitism and racism (pp. 11-
63). New York: Long Haul Press.
Razack, S. H. (1998). Looking white people in the eye:
Gender, race, and culture in courtrooms and classrooms.
Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Roediger, D. R. (1991). The wages of whiteness: Race
and the making of the American working class. London:
Verso.
Roediger, D. R. (1994). Towards the abolition of
whiteness: Essays on race, politics, and working class
history. London: Verso.
Rosenberg, P. M. (1997). Underground discourses:
Exploring whiteness in teacher education. In M. Fine, L. Weis,
L. C. Powell, & L. M. Wong (Eds.), Off White: Readings on
race, power, and society (pp. 79-89). New York: Routledge.
Spelman, E. V. (1988). Inessential woman: Problems of
exclusion in feminist thought. Boston: Beacon Press.
Thompson, A. (1998, March). Against: Logical, linear,
analytic forms of argumentation. Alternative session of the
Philosophy of Education Society, Boston, MA. [Available online
at http://www.ed.uiuc.edu/EPS/PES/debate_thompson.html.]
Thompson, B., & White Women Challenging Racism. (1997).
Home/work: Antiracism activism and the meaning of whiteness.
In M. Fine, L. Weis, L. C. Powell, & L. M. Wong (Eds.), Off
White: Readings on race, power, and society (pp. 354-366).
New York: Routledge.
Weis, L., Proweller, A., & Centrie, C. (1997). Re-
examining "A moment in history": Loss of privilege inside white
working-class masculinity in the 1990s. In M. Fine, L. Weis, L.
C. Powell, & L. M. Wong (Eds.), Off White: Readings on race,
power, and society (pp. 210-226). New York: Routledge.
Winant, H. (1997). Behind blue eyes: Whiteness and
contemporary U. S. racial politics. In M. Fine, L. Weis, L. C.
Powell, & L. M. Wong (Eds.), Off White: Readings on race,
power, and society (pp. 40-53). New York: Routledge.
Woodson, C. G. (1933/1972). The mis-education of the
Negro. Washington, DC: The Associated Publishers.
Yamato, G. (1990). Something about the subject makes it
hard to name. In G. Anzaldúa (Ed.), Making face, making
soul/Haciendo caras: Creative and critical perspectives by
women of color (pp. 20-24). San Francisco: Aunt Lute
Foundation Books.
Zane, N. (1997). Interrupting historical patterns:
Bridging race and gender gaps between senior white men and other
organizational groups. In M. Fine, L. Weis, L. C. Powell, & L.
M. Wong (Eds.), Off White: Readings on race, power, and
society (pp. 343-353). New York: Routledge.
About the Author
Audrey Thompson
Thompson@gse.utah.edu
Audrey Thompson is an associate professor of philosophy of
education and gender studies at the University of Utah. Her
areas of study include feminist and anti-racist pedagogy and
epistemology. Her publications have appeared in Educational
Theory, Harvard Educational Review, Curriculum Inquiry, McGill
Journal of Education, Journal of Thought, Educational
Foundations, Educational Studies, and the Journal of
Scholarly Publishing, as well as other journals and books.
|